• =?UTF-8?Q?Re=3A_N_to_=E2=88=9E_steps_of_D_correctly_simulated_H_nev?= =

    From Fred. Zwarts@21:1/5 to All on Mon Feb 5 10:52:49 2024
    XPost: sci.logic

    Op 05.feb.2024 om 05:19 schreef olcott:
    On 2/4/2024 9:37 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 10:14 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 8:29 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 8:44 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 5:49 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 4:14 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 12:16 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 1:02 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 11:45 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 10:53 AM, olcott wrote:
    An analytic expression x is any expression of language
    verified as
    completely true (or false) entirely on the basis that x (or >>>>>>>>>>> ~x) is
    derived by applying truth preserving operations to other >>>>>>>>>>> expressions
    of language that are stipulated to be true thus providing the >>>>>>>>>>> semantic
    meaning of terms.

    Right


    ...14 Every epistemological antinomy can likewise be used for >>>>>>>>>>> a similar undecidability proof...(Gödel 1931:43)


    WHich you just don't understand what they did.

    When we understand that a True(L, x) predicate only applies >>>>>>>>>>> to analytic
    expressions then Tarski's proof utterly fails because
    epistemological antinomies are rejected as not analytic.

    So, the fact that the EXISTANCE of a computabe True(L, x), >>>>>>>>>> allows the proving of that an epistemological antinomy must >>>>>>>>>> say that such a thing can not exist doesn't matter to you? >>>>>>>>>>

    A truth predicate only deals with analytic expressions, everything >>>>>>>>> else is out-of-scope. A truth predicate rejects expressions that >>>>>>>>> are not analytic.


    A Truth Predicate needs to deal with ALL expressions in the
    Language.
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies

    It must say they are not true, (and not false).


    That would also work, yet we construe not true and not false
    as not truth bearer thus out-of-scope of a truth predicate.

    But they are answer of different predicates.

    We only need to Truth predicate and this must reject
    epistemological antinomies. Neither Tarski nor Gödel
    understood this.

    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*
    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*
    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*

    But you don't understand what he is doing,




    Just like a Halt Decider must handle all programs definable in >>>>>>>> the system.
    This is not the same because D correctly simulated by H cannot
    possibly
    reach the self-contradiction.

    No, because the only H that "Correctly Simulates" its input is the >>>>>> one that never aborts it.


    You continue to fail to understand that correctly simulating N steps >>>>> <IS> a correct simulation of these N steps.

    But NOT a "Correct Simulation" that allows the use of a the
    simulation to replace the behavior of the machine described.


    Both Hehner and Stoddart agree that:
    D does specify non terminating behavior to H.


    *Maybe these are finally the right words*
    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D correctly simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.

    Lets call the H that aborts after N steps HaN.
    For each of these we can create a DaN based on this HaN.


    It *is* the case that a halt decider must compute
    the mapping from the behavior that its finite string
    specifies...


    HaN(DaN,DaN) must judge in input, which contains HaN, which aborts after
    N steps and therefore DaN halts. It should not judge its non-input the
    DaM, which aborts after M steps. (With M ≠ N.) There is no N for which
    HaH gets a correct result for HaN(DaN,DaN).

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Mon Feb 5 07:33:00 2024
    XPost: sci.logic

    On 2/4/24 11:19 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 9:37 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 10:14 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 8:29 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 8:44 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 5:49 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 4:14 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 12:16 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 1:02 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 11:45 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 10:53 AM, olcott wrote:
    An analytic expression x is any expression of language
    verified as
    completely true (or false) entirely on the basis that x (or >>>>>>>>>>> ~x) is
    derived by applying truth preserving operations to other >>>>>>>>>>> expressions
    of language that are stipulated to be true thus providing the >>>>>>>>>>> semantic
    meaning of terms.

    Right


    ...14 Every epistemological antinomy can likewise be used for >>>>>>>>>>> a similar undecidability proof...(Gödel 1931:43)


    WHich you just don't understand what they did.

    When we understand that a True(L, x) predicate only applies >>>>>>>>>>> to analytic
    expressions then Tarski's proof utterly fails because
    epistemological antinomies are rejected as not analytic.

    So, the fact that the EXISTANCE of a computabe True(L, x), >>>>>>>>>> allows the proving of that an epistemological antinomy must >>>>>>>>>> say that such a thing can not exist doesn't matter to you? >>>>>>>>>>

    A truth predicate only deals with analytic expressions, everything >>>>>>>>> else is out-of-scope. A truth predicate rejects expressions that >>>>>>>>> are not analytic.


    A Truth Predicate needs to deal with ALL expressions in the
    Language.
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies

    It must say they are not true, (and not false).


    That would also work, yet we construe not true and not false
    as not truth bearer thus out-of-scope of a truth predicate.

    But they are answer of different predicates.

    We only need to Truth predicate and this must reject
    epistemological antinomies. Neither Tarski nor Gödel
    understood this.

    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*
    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*
    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*

    But you don't understand what he is doing,




    Just like a Halt Decider must handle all programs definable in >>>>>>>> the system.
    This is not the same because D correctly simulated by H cannot
    possibly
    reach the self-contradiction.

    No, because the only H that "Correctly Simulates" its input is the >>>>>> one that never aborts it.


    You continue to fail to understand that correctly simulating N steps >>>>> <IS> a correct simulation of these N steps.

    But NOT a "Correct Simulation" that allows the use of a the
    simulation to replace the behavior of the machine described.


    Both Hehner and Stoddart agree that:
    D does specify non terminating behavior to H.


    *Maybe these are finally the right words*
    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D correctly simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.

    It *is* the case that a halt decider must compute
    the mapping from the behavior that its finite string
    specifies...


    So, you are just agreeing that your H is just a POOP decider, not a Halt Decider.

    If your criteria is not the actual Halting Question, your results aren't
    a Halt Decider,

    For a Halt Decider, it must compute the mapping from the finite input
    string to the behavior that string specifies, and that string specifies
    a Compuation, and the FULL sequnece of states that running it will
    generate, and we ask if the sequence has an end.

    It is NOT about can H simulate that input to the end, but does it have one.

    And, for this case, the input is built on a copy of the EXACT
    computation that is deciding on it.

    You don't get to change the criteria to something that creates a
    different map.

    You clearly don't understand the nature of requirements, and thus the
    meaning of "Correct" or "True"

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Fred. Zwarts@21:1/5 to All on Mon Feb 5 15:58:01 2024
    XPost: sci.logic

    Op 05.feb.2024 om 15:28 schreef olcott:
    On 2/5/2024 3:52 AM, Fred. Zwarts wrote:
    Op 05.feb.2024 om 05:19 schreef olcott:
    On 2/4/2024 9:37 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 10:14 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 8:29 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 8:44 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 5:49 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 4:14 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 12:16 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 1:02 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 11:45 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 10:53 AM, olcott wrote:
    An analytic expression x is any expression of language >>>>>>>>>>>>> verified as
    completely true (or false) entirely on the basis that x (or >>>>>>>>>>>>> ~x) is
    derived by applying truth preserving operations to other >>>>>>>>>>>>> expressions
    of language that are stipulated to be true thus providing >>>>>>>>>>>>> the semantic
    meaning of terms.

    Right


    ...14 Every epistemological antinomy can likewise be used >>>>>>>>>>>>> for a similar undecidability proof...(Gödel 1931:43) >>>>>>>>>>>>>

    WHich you just don't understand what they did.

    When we understand that a True(L, x) predicate only applies >>>>>>>>>>>>> to analytic
    expressions then Tarski's proof utterly fails because >>>>>>>>>>>>> epistemological antinomies are rejected as not analytic. >>>>>>>>>>>>
    So, the fact that the EXISTANCE of a computabe True(L, x), >>>>>>>>>>>> allows the proving of that an epistemological antinomy must >>>>>>>>>>>> say that such a thing can not exist doesn't matter to you? >>>>>>>>>>>>

    A truth predicate only deals with analytic expressions,
    everything
    else is out-of-scope. A truth predicate rejects expressions that >>>>>>>>>>> are not analytic.


    A Truth Predicate needs to deal with ALL expressions in the >>>>>>>>>> Language.
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies

    It must say they are not true, (and not false).


    That would also work, yet we construe not true and not false
    as not truth bearer thus out-of-scope of a truth predicate.

    But they are answer of different predicates.

    We only need to Truth predicate and this must reject
    epistemological antinomies. Neither Tarski nor Gödel
    understood this.

    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*
    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*
    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*

    But you don't understand what he is doing,




    Just like a Halt Decider must handle all programs definable in >>>>>>>>>> the system.
    This is not the same because D correctly simulated by H cannot >>>>>>>>> possibly
    reach the self-contradiction.

    No, because the only H that "Correctly Simulates" its input is >>>>>>>> the one that never aborts it.


    You continue to fail to understand that correctly simulating N steps >>>>>>> <IS> a correct simulation of these N steps.

    But NOT a "Correct Simulation" that allows the use of a the
    simulation to replace the behavior of the machine described.


    Both Hehner and Stoddart agree that:
    D does specify non terminating behavior to H.


    *Maybe these are finally the right words*
    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D correctly simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.

    Lets call the H that aborts after N steps HaN.
    For each of these we can create a DaN based on this HaN.

    When H correctly reports on the behavior of every H that can
    possibly exist we need no other H.


    It *is* the case that a halt decider must compute
    the mapping from the behavior that its finite string
    specifies...


    HaN(DaN,DaN) must judge in input, which contains HaN, which aborts
    after N steps and therefore DaN halts. It should not judge its
    non-input the DaM, which aborts after M steps. (With M ≠ N.) There is
    no N for which HaH gets a correct result for HaN(DaN,DaN).


    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D correctly simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.


    Each of the DaN specify that it reaches the final state, so, if H
    aborts, there is no D that does not reach the final state.

    As soon as H correctly determines that the above is
    true in N steps of correct simulation then H correctly
    aborts its simulated and rejects D as non-halting.


    None of the HaN correctly simulate DaN, because they all need to
    simulate a few steps more than they do. A H that simulates N steps and
    more than N steps at the same time does not exist. So, there is no H
    that correctly determines that the above is true in N steps, because it
    always needs more steps than N. If H simulates N steps, it needs a few
    steps more to see that DaN returns. No correct HaN exists, not even in
    the limit N → ∞.
    Remember That HaN(DaN,DaN) must decide on its input DaN, not on its
    non-input DaM, with M ≠ N.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Fred. Zwarts@21:1/5 to All on Mon Feb 5 16:43:59 2024
    XPost: sci.logic

    Op 05.feb.2024 om 16:15 schreef olcott:
    On 2/5/2024 8:58 AM, Fred. Zwarts wrote:
    Op 05.feb.2024 om 15:28 schreef olcott:
    On 2/5/2024 3:52 AM, Fred. Zwarts wrote:
    Op 05.feb.2024 om 05:19 schreef olcott:
    On 2/4/2024 9:37 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 10:14 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 8:29 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 8:44 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 5:49 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 4:14 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 12:16 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 1:02 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 11:45 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 10:53 AM, olcott wrote:
    An analytic expression x is any expression of language >>>>>>>>>>>>>>> verified as
    completely true (or false) entirely on the basis that x >>>>>>>>>>>>>>> (or ~x) is
    derived by applying truth preserving operations to other >>>>>>>>>>>>>>> expressions
    of language that are stipulated to be true thus providing >>>>>>>>>>>>>>> the semantic
    meaning of terms.

    Right


    ...14 Every epistemological antinomy can likewise be used >>>>>>>>>>>>>>> for a similar undecidability proof...(Gödel 1931:43) >>>>>>>>>>>>>>>

    WHich you just don't understand what they did.

    When we understand that a True(L, x) predicate only >>>>>>>>>>>>>>> applies to analytic
    expressions then Tarski's proof utterly fails because >>>>>>>>>>>>>>> epistemological antinomies are rejected as not analytic. >>>>>>>>>>>>>>
    So, the fact that the EXISTANCE of a computabe True(L, x), >>>>>>>>>>>>>> allows the proving of that an epistemological antinomy >>>>>>>>>>>>>> must say that such a thing can not exist doesn't matter to >>>>>>>>>>>>>> you?


    A truth predicate only deals with analytic expressions, >>>>>>>>>>>>> everything
    else is out-of-scope. A truth predicate rejects expressions >>>>>>>>>>>>> that
    are not analytic.


    A Truth Predicate needs to deal with ALL expressions in the >>>>>>>>>>>> Language.
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies

    It must say they are not true, (and not false).


    That would also work, yet we construe not true and not false >>>>>>>>> as not truth bearer thus out-of-scope of a truth predicate.

    But they are answer of different predicates.

    We only need to Truth predicate and this must reject
    epistemological antinomies. Neither Tarski nor Gödel
    understood this.

    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*
    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*
    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*

    But you don't understand what he is doing,




    Just like a Halt Decider must handle all programs definable >>>>>>>>>>>> in the system.
    This is not the same because D correctly simulated by H
    cannot possibly
    reach the self-contradiction.

    No, because the only H that "Correctly Simulates" its input is >>>>>>>>>> the one that never aborts it.


    You continue to fail to understand that correctly simulating N >>>>>>>>> steps
    <IS> a correct simulation of these N steps.

    But NOT a "Correct Simulation" that allows the use of a the
    simulation to replace the behavior of the machine described.


    Both Hehner and Stoddart agree that:
    D does specify non terminating behavior to H.


    *Maybe these are finally the right words*
    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D correctly simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.

    Lets call the H that aborts after N steps HaN.
    For each of these we can create a DaN based on this HaN.

    When H correctly reports on the behavior of every H that can
    possibly exist we need no other H.


    It *is* the case that a halt decider must compute
    the mapping from the behavior that its finite string
    specifies...


    HaN(DaN,DaN) must judge in input, which contains HaN, which aborts
    after N steps and therefore DaN halts. It should not judge its
    non-input the DaM, which aborts after M steps. (With M ≠ N.) There
    is no N for which HaH gets a correct result for HaN(DaN,DaN).


    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D correctly simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.


    Each of the DaN specify that it reaches the final state, so, if H
    aborts, there is no D that does not reach the final state.

    As soon as H correctly determines that the above is
    true in N steps of correct simulation then H correctly
    aborts its simulated and rejects D as non-halting.


    None of the HaN correctly simulate DaN, because they all need to

    Of the infinite set of every H1...Hn that correctly simulates
    1 to ∞ steps of its corresponding D1...Dn none of these infinite
    pairs ever reaches its own final state.

    That should be:
    Of the infinite set of every H1...Hn that simulates 1 to n steps, none simulates enough steps to see that D1 halts normally. So, they all abort
    too soon and return falsely an non-halting state.


    The specific H that correctly simulates N steps of D correctly
    determines that above is true (for the entire infinite set)
    thus providing it with the correct halt status criteria basis
    to reject D as non-halting.


    That should be:
    The fact that a true simulator that simulates Dn with enough steps halts normally, proves that this is true for the entire infinite set, thus
    proving that none of these H1...Hn correctly report a non-halting state.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Fred. Zwarts@21:1/5 to All on Mon Feb 5 17:06:18 2024
    XPost: sci.logic

    Op 05.feb.2024 om 16:43 schreef Fred. Zwarts:
    Op 05.feb.2024 om 16:15 schreef olcott:
    On 2/5/2024 8:58 AM, Fred. Zwarts wrote:
    Op 05.feb.2024 om 15:28 schreef olcott:
    On 2/5/2024 3:52 AM, Fred. Zwarts wrote:
    Op 05.feb.2024 om 05:19 schreef olcott:
    On 2/4/2024 9:37 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 10:14 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 8:29 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 8:44 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 5:49 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 4:14 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 12:16 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 1:02 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 11:45 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 10:53 AM, olcott wrote:
    An analytic expression x is any expression of language >>>>>>>>>>>>>>>> verified as
    completely true (or false) entirely on the basis that x >>>>>>>>>>>>>>>> (or ~x) is
    derived by applying truth preserving operations to other >>>>>>>>>>>>>>>> expressions
    of language that are stipulated to be true thus >>>>>>>>>>>>>>>> providing the semantic
    meaning of terms.

    Right


    ...14 Every epistemological antinomy can likewise be >>>>>>>>>>>>>>>> used for a similar undecidability proof...(Gödel 1931:43) >>>>>>>>>>>>>>>>

    WHich you just don't understand what they did.

    When we understand that a True(L, x) predicate only >>>>>>>>>>>>>>>> applies to analytic
    expressions then Tarski's proof utterly fails because >>>>>>>>>>>>>>>> epistemological antinomies are rejected as not analytic. >>>>>>>>>>>>>>>
    So, the fact that the EXISTANCE of a computabe True(L, >>>>>>>>>>>>>>> x), allows the proving of that an epistemological >>>>>>>>>>>>>>> antinomy must say that such a thing can not exist doesn't >>>>>>>>>>>>>>> matter to you?


    A truth predicate only deals with analytic expressions, >>>>>>>>>>>>>> everything
    else is out-of-scope. A truth predicate rejects
    expressions that
    are not analytic.


    A Truth Predicate needs to deal with ALL expressions in the >>>>>>>>>>>>> Language.
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies

    It must say they are not true, (and not false).


    That would also work, yet we construe not true and not false >>>>>>>>>> as not truth bearer thus out-of-scope of a truth predicate. >>>>>>>>>
    But they are answer of different predicates.

    We only need to Truth predicate and this must reject
    epistemological antinomies. Neither Tarski nor Gödel
    understood this.

    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*
    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*
    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*

    But you don't understand what he is doing,




    Just like a Halt Decider must handle all programs definable >>>>>>>>>>>>> in the system.
    This is not the same because D correctly simulated by H >>>>>>>>>>>> cannot possibly
    reach the self-contradiction.

    No, because the only H that "Correctly Simulates" its input >>>>>>>>>>> is the one that never aborts it.


    You continue to fail to understand that correctly simulating N >>>>>>>>>> steps
    <IS> a correct simulation of these N steps.

    But NOT a "Correct Simulation" that allows the use of a the
    simulation to replace the behavior of the machine described. >>>>>>>>>

    Both Hehner and Stoddart agree that:
    D does specify non terminating behavior to H.


    *Maybe these are finally the right words*
    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D correctly simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.

    Lets call the H that aborts after N steps HaN.
    For each of these we can create a DaN based on this HaN.

    When H correctly reports on the behavior of every H that can
    possibly exist we need no other H.


    It *is* the case that a halt decider must compute
    the mapping from the behavior that its finite string
    specifies...


    HaN(DaN,DaN) must judge in input, which contains HaN, which aborts
    after N steps and therefore DaN halts. It should not judge its
    non-input the DaM, which aborts after M steps. (With M ≠ N.) There >>>>> is no N for which HaH gets a correct result for HaN(DaN,DaN).


    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D correctly simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.


    Each of the DaN specify that it reaches the final state, so, if H
    aborts, there is no D that does not reach the final state.

    As soon as H correctly determines that the above is
    true in N steps of correct simulation then H correctly
    aborts its simulated and rejects D as non-halting.


    None of the HaN correctly simulate DaN, because they all need to

    Of the infinite set of every H1...Hn that correctly simulates
    1 to ∞ steps of its corresponding D1...Dn none of these infinite
    pairs ever reaches its own final state.

    That should be:
    Of the infinite set of every H1...Hn that simulates 1 to n steps, none simulates enough steps to see that D1 halts normally. So, they all abort
    too soon and return falsely an non-halting state.

    D1 should be Dn.



    The specific H that correctly simulates N steps of D correctly
    determines that above is true (for the entire infinite set)
    thus providing it with the correct halt status criteria basis
    to reject D as non-halting.


    That should be:
    The fact that a true simulator that simulates Dn with enough steps halts normally, proves that this is true for the entire infinite set, thus
    proving that none of these H1...Hn correctly report a non-halting state.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From immibis@21:1/5 to olcott on Mon Feb 5 20:32:34 2024
    XPost: sci.logic

    On 5/02/24 05:19, olcott wrote:

    *Maybe these are finally the right words*
    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D correctly simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.

    It is impossible to simulate ∞ steps.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From immibis@21:1/5 to olcott on Mon Feb 5 20:31:03 2024
    XPost: sci.logic

    On 5/02/24 19:21, olcott wrote:
    On 2/5/2024 9:43 AM, Fred. Zwarts wrote:
    Op 05.feb.2024 om 16:15 schreef olcott:
    On 2/5/2024 8:58 AM, Fred. Zwarts wrote:

    None of the HaN correctly simulate DaN, because they all need to

    Of the infinite set of every H1...Hn that correctly simulates
    1 to ∞ steps of its corresponding D1...Dn none of these infinite
    pairs ever reaches its own final state.

    That should be:
    Of the infinite set of every H1...Hn that simulates 1 to n steps, none
    simulates enough steps to see that D1 halts normally. So, they all
    abort too soon and return falsely an non-halting state.


    According to your reasoning no one has any idea that
    Infinite_Loop() is an infinite loop until they run
    it and wait until the end of time to find out that
    it never halts.

    void Infinite_Loop()
    {
      HERE: goto HERE;
    }

    It is impossible for a simulating termination analyser to analyse
    termination by any method other than simulation. If a termination
    analyser uses something other than simulation, it is not as simulating termination analyser.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From immibis@21:1/5 to olcott on Mon Feb 5 21:59:52 2024
    XPost: sci.logic

    On 5/02/24 15:18, olcott wrote:

    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D *correctly* simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.

    This doesn't make sense. You can't simulate ∞ steps.

    Innovation DOES CHANGE THINGS.
    No one ever thought of a simulating halt decider before.

    Simulation was literally everyone's first thought when they thought
    about how to make a halt decider. They thought some more, and realized
    that it doesn't work and can't work.

    Everyone that thought of simulation rejected it as a basis.

    Because it doesn't work.


    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D *correctly* simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.

    This doesn't make sense. You can't simulate ∞ steps.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Mon Feb 5 22:58:19 2024
    XPost: sci.logic

    On 2/5/24 9:28 AM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/5/2024 3:52 AM, Fred. Zwarts wrote:
    Op 05.feb.2024 om 05:19 schreef olcott:
    On 2/4/2024 9:37 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 10:14 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 8:29 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 8:44 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 5:49 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 4:14 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 12:16 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 1:02 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 11:45 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 2/4/24 10:53 AM, olcott wrote:
    An analytic expression x is any expression of language >>>>>>>>>>>>> verified as
    completely true (or false) entirely on the basis that x (or >>>>>>>>>>>>> ~x) is
    derived by applying truth preserving operations to other >>>>>>>>>>>>> expressions
    of language that are stipulated to be true thus providing >>>>>>>>>>>>> the semantic
    meaning of terms.

    Right


    ...14 Every epistemological antinomy can likewise be used >>>>>>>>>>>>> for a similar undecidability proof...(Gödel 1931:43) >>>>>>>>>>>>>

    WHich you just don't understand what they did.

    When we understand that a True(L, x) predicate only applies >>>>>>>>>>>>> to analytic
    expressions then Tarski's proof utterly fails because >>>>>>>>>>>>> epistemological antinomies are rejected as not analytic. >>>>>>>>>>>>
    So, the fact that the EXISTANCE of a computabe True(L, x), >>>>>>>>>>>> allows the proving of that an epistemological antinomy must >>>>>>>>>>>> say that such a thing can not exist doesn't matter to you? >>>>>>>>>>>>

    A truth predicate only deals with analytic expressions,
    everything
    else is out-of-scope. A truth predicate rejects expressions that >>>>>>>>>>> are not analytic.


    A Truth Predicate needs to deal with ALL expressions in the >>>>>>>>>> Language.
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies
    IT MUST REJECT epistemological antinomies

    It must say they are not true, (and not false).


    That would also work, yet we construe not true and not false
    as not truth bearer thus out-of-scope of a truth predicate.

    But they are answer of different predicates.

    We only need to Truth predicate and this must reject
    epistemological antinomies. Neither Tarski nor Gödel
    understood this.

    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*
    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*
    *That is the key essence of their huge mistake*

    But you don't understand what he is doing,




    Just like a Halt Decider must handle all programs definable in >>>>>>>>>> the system.
    This is not the same because D correctly simulated by H cannot >>>>>>>>> possibly
    reach the self-contradiction.

    No, because the only H that "Correctly Simulates" its input is >>>>>>>> the one that never aborts it.


    You continue to fail to understand that correctly simulating N steps >>>>>>> <IS> a correct simulation of these N steps.

    But NOT a "Correct Simulation" that allows the use of a the
    simulation to replace the behavior of the machine described.


    Both Hehner and Stoddart agree that:
    D does specify non terminating behavior to H.


    *Maybe these are finally the right words*
    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D correctly simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.

    Lets call the H that aborts after N steps HaN.
    For each of these we can create a DaN based on this HaN.

    When H correctly reports on the behavior of every H that can
    possibly exist we need no other H.

    And when if incorrectly reports on the actual behavior of its input, it
    is just wrong as a Halt decider.

    You are just proving you have POOP on your brain.



    It *is* the case that a halt decider must compute
    the mapping from the behavior that its finite string
    specifies...


    HaN(DaN,DaN) must judge in input, which contains HaN, which aborts
    after N steps and therefore DaN halts. It should not judge its
    non-input the DaM, which aborts after M steps. (With M ≠ N.) There is
    no N for which HaH gets a correct result for HaN(DaN,DaN).


    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D correctly simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.

    But once you fix the H to a given number of steps, then


    As soon as H correctly determines that the above is
    true in N steps of correct simulation then H correctly
    aborts its simulated and rejects D as non-halting.



    So H is just a correct POOP decider, but not a Halt Decider, since a
    Halt Decider needs to answer about the behavior of the specific input
    given to it, and for any H that aborts this input and returns
    non-halting, that input, which was based on THAT specific H, will halt
    when run, and no H in your set every correctly simulated that specific
    input (as the only one that was given it, incorrectly gave up too soon).

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to immibis on Mon Feb 5 22:58:28 2024
    XPost: sci.logic

    On 2/5/24 2:32 PM, immibis wrote:
    On 5/02/24 05:19, olcott wrote:

    *Maybe these are finally the right words*
    D specifies that N to ∞ steps of D correctly simulated
    by H cannot possibly reach the final state of D.

    It is impossible to simulate ∞ steps.


    No, depending on your exact definitions, you can simulate an infinite
    number of steps, just not in finite time, which means the simulator can
    not be a decider.

    A UTM given the description of a Non-Halting compuation will simulate it
    for an infinite number of steps.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)