• Why Einstein was wrong about relativity

    From solarlibration@gmail.com@21:1/5 to All on Sat Jul 21 04:43:06 2018
    On Friday, October 31, 2008 at 1:29:42 PM UTC, ©Haos wrote:
    Why Einstein was wrong about relativity

    * 29 October 2008
    * NewScientist.com
    * Mark Buchanan

    IMAGINE you are on a bicycle, pedalling across the cosmos. A beam of
    light - perhaps sent off by a distant collapsing star - zings past
    you. How fast are you and the light approaching each other? You are travelling at hardly any speed, so the answer will be more or less
    exactly light's speed through the interstellar vacuum, around 300
    million metres a second.

    Now imagine you abandon pedal power for the day. Bowling along in your spaceship at half light speed, you meet another light pulse head-on.
    What is your speed of approach now? Surely it is just your speed plus
    that of the light: in total, one and a half times light speed.

    Wrong. Your speed of approach will be the speed of light, no more -
    and that's true however fast you are travelling. Welcome to the weird
    world of Einstein's special relativity, where as things move faster
    they shrink, and where time gets so distorted that even talking about
    events being simultaneous is pointless. That all follows, as Albert
    Einstein showed, from the fact that light always travels at the same
    speed, however you look at it.

    Really? Mitchell Feigenbaum, a physicist at The Rockefeller University
    in New York, begs to differ. He's the latest and most prominent in a
    line of researchers insisting that Einstein's theory has nothing to do
    with light - whatever history and the textbooks might say. "Not only
    is it not necessary," he says, "but there's absolutely no room in the
    theory for it."

    What's more, Feigenbaum claims in a paper on the arXiv preprint server
    that has yet to be peer-reviewed, if only the father of relativity,
    Galileo Galilei, had known a little more modern mathematics back in
    the 17th century, he could have got as far as Einstein did (www.arxiv.org/abs/0806.1234). "Galileo's thoughts are almost 400
    years old," he says. "But they're still extraordinarily potent.
    They're enough on their own to give Einstein's relativity, without any additional knowledge."

    The claim has got other physicists thinking. Take Feigenbaum's
    argument a step further, some say, and we might long ago have seen our
    way not only to Einstein's relativity but also to the idea of an
    expanding universe - even one whose expansion is accelerating -
    without the intellectual upheavals that have led us to those
    conclusions today.

    The discussion centres on two assumptions that Einstein made when
    formulating his special theory of relativity in 1905. The first is uncontroversial: that the laws of physics should look the same to
    anyone at rest or moving steadily. Say I am standing motionless and
    you are moving past on a train travelling at a constant speed in a
    straight line - in other words, at a constant velocity. To you on the
    train, I am the one who seems to be moving. But it does not actually
    matter who is "really" moving relative to whom: although perceived
    velocities depend on one's point of view, the physical laws governing
    motion stay the same.

    This is the principle of relativity proposed by Galileo in A Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems, his treatise of 1632 that got
    him into hot water with the Catholic church for discussing
    Copernicus's idea that Earth goes round the sun. Galileo writes of a passenger inside a ship who cannot tell if it is moving or standing
    still "so long as the motion is uniform and not fluctuating this way
    and that". The analogy was aimed at those sceptics who believed that
    Earth could not be moving because they could not feel it.

    Galileo's relativity served well for almost 250 years. But when
    Scottish physicist James Clerk Maxwell derived his theory of
    electricity and magnetism in the late 19th century, it hit a snag.
    Maxwell's equations make clear that light is a wave travelling at a
    constant speed. But oddly, they do not mention from whose point of
    view this speed is measured.

    This was a problem if Maxwell's theory, like all good physical
    theories, was to follow Galileo's rule and apply for everyone. If we
    do not know who measures the speed of light in the equations, how can
    we modify them to apply from other perspectives? Einstein's workaround
    was that we don't have to. Faced with the success of Maxwell's theory,
    he simply added a second assumption to Galileo's first: that, relative
    to any observer, light always travels at the same speed.

    This "second postulate" is the source of all Einstein's eccentric
    physics of shrinking space and haywire clocks. And with a little
    further thought, it leads to the equivalence of mass and energy
    embodied in the iconic equation E = mc2. The argument is not about the physics, which countless experiments have confirmed. It is about
    whether we can reach the same conclusions without hoisting light onto
    its highly irregular pedestal.

    According to David Mermin, who has been teaching relativity at Cornell University in Ithaca, New York, for 30 years, a consensus has emerged
    that we can, although this shift has yet to filter through to a wider audience. "All the textbooks teach relativity based on Einstein's principles," he says. "And there's an extremely widespread
    misunderstanding that relativity is somehow tied up with light."

    Two years ago, Feigenbaum's puzzlement with relativity's logic led him
    to Galileo's Dialogue. "The book is quite a knockout," he says. "When
    I finished reading, I wondered, if you take what he says seriously,
    what can you produce?" So he sat down and started calculating as
    Galileo might have, but using today's more sophisticated mathematics.

    He starts with a simple scenario. You are standing watching a friend,
    Frank, moving past you on a train at 50 kilometres per hour towards
    the east. Frank, on the other hand, has his eyes on Kate, whom he sees receding from him at 50 km/h towards the north. Feigenbaum asks a
    simple question: how do you see Kate moving?

    It seems natural that Kate's velocity relative to you should in some
    sense be the sum of Frank's velocity relative to you and Kate's
    relative to Frank. The fact that Frank sees Kate both receding to the
    north and keeping up with his eastbound motion implies that, from your stationary point of view, her motion is towards the north-east.

    But now swap Frank and Kate's motions. Frank is travelling at 50 km/h northwards relative to you, and Kate at 50 km/h eastwards relative to
    Frank. This should not affect how Kate is travelling relative to you -
    you will still see her heading off towards the north-east.

    Galileo would certainly have said so. Only with Einstein's
    introduction of a space-time warped, as he thought, by a universal
    speed of light did it become clear that the rules of adding motions
    were not quite so simple as all that. But in fact, says Feigenbaum,
    both Galileo and Einstein missed a surprising subtlety in the maths -
    one that renders Einstein's second postulate superfluous.

    It is this: if Frank's world is aligned with yours - if the north and
    east of both you and Frank point in the same direction - and Kate's
    world is similarly aligned with Frank's, you might think that Kate's
    is aligned with yours. The problem is, mathematical logic alone does
    not permit that conclusion. Strange as it may seem, it in fact allows
    a distinct possibility that Kate's world could be rotated with respect
    to yours - even if she is perfectly aligned with Frank and Frank is
    perfectly aligned with you.

    This means that, while still seeing Kate careering off towards the north-east, you might also see her skewed slightly to the left or
    right relative to her direction of motion (see diagram). The direction
    of the rotation, and thus Kate's motion as seen by you, would depend
    on what the relative motions of you and Frank and of Frank and Kate
    are.

    The possibility of such rotations turns out to have far-reaching consequences. Ignore them, and Galileo's relativity pops out. Allow
    them, and the algebra works out very differently: the mangled space-
    time of Einstein's relativity emerges, complete with a definite but unspecified maximum speed that the sum of individual relative speeds
    cannot exceed. "These rotations are hard to understand," Feigenbaum
    says, "but they're the wellspring of physics."

    Feigenbaum emphasises that he is not the first person to question
    Einstein's second postulate or arrive at the idea of such bizarre
    rotations. Even so, Mermin is impressed. "Mitch's way of deriving the
    theory is quite complicated," he says, "but the rotations come up in a
    very natural and beautiful way."

    The result turns the historical logic of Einstein's relativity on its
    head. Those contortions of space and time that Einstein derived from
    the properties of light actually emerge from even more basic, purely mathematical considerations. Light's special position in relativity is
    a historical accident: it was just the first (and is still the most
    obvious) phenomenon we have encountered that travels at the universal
    maximum speed.

    The idea that Einstein's relativity has nothing to do with light could actually come in rather handy. For one thing, it rules out a nasty
    shock if anyone were ever to prove that photons, the particles of
    light, have mass. We know that the photon's mass is very small - less
    than 10-49 grams. A photon with any mass at all would imply that our understanding of electricity and magnetism is wrong, and that electric
    charge might not be conserved. That would be problem enough, but a
    massive photon would also spell deep trouble for the second postulate,
    as a photon with mass would not necessarily always travel at the same
    speed. Feigenbaum's work shows how, contrary to many physicists'
    beliefs, this need not be a problem for relativity.

    "Feigenbaum's ideas could be very helpful in correcting this
    misconception," says physicist Sergio Cacciatori of the University of Insubria in Como, Italy. He suggests that further thinking along
    similar lines could reveal much more about the universe. Together with
    his colleague Vittorio Gorini, and Alexander Kamenshchik of the Landau Institute for Theoretical Physics in Moscow, Russia, he has explored
    what would happen if you took Feigenbaum's conclusions about adding
    motions and applied them to changes in position (www.arxiv.org/abs/ 0807.3009). What if where you ended up after two consecutive
    displacements depended on the order of their occurrence?

    In the world around us, it is obviously a pretty good approximation to reality that, if you take 20 paces forward and 10 to the left, you end
    up in the same place as if you had taken 10 equally sized places to
    the left and then 20 forward. On the vast scales of the cosmos,
    however, the same assumption might be dangerously misleading. It
    amounts to requiring the universe to have a flat, Euclidean geometry -
    one like that in our immediate environment, in which parallel lines
    never cross and the inside angles of triangles add up to 180 degrees.

    Abandon that assumption, Cacciatori and his colleagues show, and
    things look very different. The universe is not flat and Euclidean,
    but curved in on itself, creating a geometry akin to that of the
    surface of a sphere such as Earth - where the parallel lines of
    longitude converge at the poles and the internal angles of triangles
    add up to more than 180 degrees.

    That discovery is significant because it feeds into a long-running
    debate about the shape - and fate - of the universe. Back in 1916,
    Einstein fused special relativity with Newton's ideas of gravitation
    to create a universal theory of gravity, known as the general theory
    of relativity. General relativity predicts that mass and energy warp
    space and time, and that the distribution of mass and energy
    determines the universe's geometry.
    Predictable fate

    When Einstein applied these ideas to calculate the dynamics of the
    universe, the outcome was decidedly odd: the gravity of the universe
    warps its fabric so much that it becomes unstable and collapses in on
    itself. To avoid this dispiriting and apparently nonsensical
    conclusion, Einstein added to his general relativistic brew a new
    quantity, the "cosmological constant", to counteract gravity and
    create a stable, static universe. This universe's geometry was curved
    and closed in on itself - rather like the three-dimensional surface of
    a four-dimensional sphere.

    Einstein's constant was short-lived. In 1929, Edwin Hubble found
    evidence that distant galaxies were receding from the Earth, implying
    that the universe was expanding dynamically. Faced with this evidence
    against a static universe, Einstein famously decried the constant as
    his "greatest blunder".

    Just recently, however, the cosmological constant has come back into
    fashion. The reason is the evidence accumulated by astronomers over
    the past decade - in the unexpected dimness of some extremely distant supernovae, and in the cosmic microwave background, the still-
    reverberating echo of the big bang - that the expansion of the
    universe is accelerating. That acceleration seems to require just the
    kind of anti-gravitational effect that motivated Einstein's constant
    in the first place.

    The irony, says Gorini, is that we could have seen all along that
    something like the cosmological constant makes sense. Follow the
    mathematics of relativity through to its logical conclusion, allowing
    for displacements that add up in different ways, and you find that
    space must have just the curvature that a cosmological constant helps
    to produce. That has nothing to do with the distribution of mass, but
    follows from mathematical logic alone.

    So had we put our faith in mathematical reasoning, might we have been
    able to predict the dynamics of the universe much sooner? Gorini
    thinks so. He claims that the German mathematician Hermann Minkowski
    came close to exploring these displacement effects in lectures on
    relativity he delivered in 1908. "Had he done it," Gorini says,
    "physicists would have known that the universe expands, and that its expansion is accelerated, well before the development of general
    relativity or even Hubble's observation of the recession of galaxies."

    As it happens, in 1968, physicists Henri Bacry and Jean-Marc Levy-
    LeBlond of the University of Nice in France predicted the existence of
    a cosmological constant from first principles (Journal of Mathematical Physics, vol 9, p 1605). Their work presages that of Feigenbaum and of
    Gorini and colleagues, but remained unnoticed - largely because the
    constant was out of fashion at the time.

    Against that prevailing scientific wind, it would have been a bold
    leap for those researchers to have predicted the dynamics of the
    universe; for Galileo, centuries before, even more so. Einstein, the
    ultimate physics revolutionary, probably would have afforded himself a
    wry smile at the picture that is now emerging. The startling edifice
    of the new physics he built remains undisturbed, even as its logical foundations are being greatly strengthened. Meanwhile, the power of mathematical reasoning in unlocking the secrets of the universe
    continues to amaze: what physicist Eugene Wigner once called "the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics" is one of the deepest
    mysteries of them all.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)