• The braking of the traveler twin

    From Luigi Fortunati@21:1/5 to All on Mon Mar 14 12:08:08 2022
    The traveling twin starts and travels for 4 years at speed v = 0.866c
    and then brakes, as seen in the animation
    https://www.geogebra.org/m/jzc4amud

    Calculate the Earth-spaceship distance, before and after braking (in
    the spaceship reference).

    Calculate how many turns the Earth has made around the sun, before and
    after braking (in the spaceship reference).

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Luigi Fortunati on Tue Mar 15 08:36:02 2022
    On 3/14/22 1:08 PM, Luigi Fortunati wrote:
    The traveling twin starts and travels for 4 years at speed v = 0.866c
    and then brakes, as seen in the animation
    https://www.geogebra.org/m/jzc4amud

    Calculate the Earth-spaceship distance, before and after braking (in
    the spaceship reference).

    Calculate how many turns the Earth has made around the sun, before and
    after braking (in the spaceship reference).


    Suppose the two twins have just been born when the traveling twin starts
    his trip. So they are each zero years old then. If the traveling twin
    (he) travels for 4 years of his time, he will be 4 yours old when he
    stops. (His age when he stops is an EVENT that all observers must agree
    about, and so she also agrees that he is 4 years old when he stops. He
    says he has traveled (0.866)(4) = 3.464 lightyears away from his twin
    (her) then. She says he traveled 8 years of her time ... i.e., she says
    she is 8 years old when he stops. She says he is (0.866)(8) = 6.928
    lightyears away when he stops.

    After he stops, she says that he remains 6.928 lightyears away from her
    after that. And she says they age at the same rate after he stops. He
    says that, during his essentially instantaneous stopping time, his age essentially doesn't change during his stopping. She agrees with that.
    But he says that during his essentially instantaneous stopping, SHE
    essentially instantaneously gets older by 4 years ... i.e., he says that
    she essentially instantaneously goes from being 4 years old to being 8
    years old during the essentially instantaneous time in his life it takes
    him to stop. And he also says that their distance apart essentially instantaneously increases from 3.464 lightyears to 6.928 lightyears
    while he is doing his essentially instantaneous stopping.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Luigi Fortunati@21:1/5 to All on Tue Mar 15 12:28:40 2022
    Mike Fontenot martedì 15/03/2022 alle ore 09:36:02 ha scritto:
    The traveling twin starts and travels for 4 years at speed v = 0.866c
    and then brakes, as seen in the animation
    https://www.geogebra.org/m/jzc4amud

    Calculate the Earth-spaceship distance, before and after braking (in
    the spaceship reference).

    Calculate how many turns the Earth has made around the sun, before and
    after braking (in the spaceship reference).


    Suppose the two twins have just been born when the traveling twin starts
    his trip. So they are each zero years old then. If the traveling twin
    (he) travels for 4 years of his time, he will be 4 yours old when he
    stops. (His age when he stops is an EVENT that all observers must agree about, and so she also agrees that he is 4 years old when he stops. He
    says he has traveled (0.866)(4) = 3.464 lightyears away from his twin
    (her) then. She says he traveled 8 years of her time ... i.e., she says
    she is 8 years old when he stops. She says he is (0.866)(8) = 6.928 lightyears away when he stops.

    After he stops, she says that he remains 6.928 lightyears away from her
    after that. And she says they age at the same rate after he stops. He
    says that, during his essentially instantaneous stopping time, his age essentially doesn't change during his stopping. She agrees with that.
    But he says that during his essentially instantaneous stopping, SHE essentially instantaneously gets older by 4 years ... i.e., he says that
    she essentially instantaneously goes from being 4 years old to being 8
    years old during the essentially instantaneous time in his life it takes
    him to stop. And he also says that their distance apart essentially instantaneously increases from 3.464 lightyears to 6.928 lightyears
    while he is doing his essentially instantaneous stopping.

    Ok.

    And how many turns around the Sun did the Earth make just before and immediately after the stop, in the spaceship reference?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Livingston@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Tue Mar 15 13:55:06 2022
    On Tuesday, March 15, 2022 at 3:36:07 AM UTC-5, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 3/14/22 1:08 PM, Luigi Fortunati wrote:
    The traveling twin starts and travels for 4 years at speed v = 0.866c
    and then brakes, as seen in the animation https://www.geogebra.org/m/jzc4amud

    Calculate the Earth-spaceship distance, before and after braking (in
    the spaceship reference).

    Calculate how many turns the Earth has made around the sun, before and after braking (in the spaceship reference).

    Suppose the two twins have just been born when the traveling twin starts
    his trip. So they are each zero years old then. If the traveling twin
    (he) travels for 4 years of his time, he will be 4 yours old when he
    stops. (His age when he stops is an EVENT that all observers must agree about, and so she also agrees that he is 4 years old when he stops. He
    says he has traveled (0.866)(4) = 3.464 lightyears away from his twin
    (her) then. She says he traveled 8 years of her time ... i.e., she says
    she is 8 years old when he stops. She says he is (0.866)(8) = 6.928 lightyears away when he stops.

    After he stops, she says that he remains 6.928 lightyears away from her
    after that. And she says they age at the same rate after he stops. He
    says that, during his essentially instantaneous stopping time, his age essentially doesn't change during his stopping. She agrees with that.
    But he says that during his essentially instantaneous stopping, SHE essentially instantaneously gets older by 4 years ... i.e., he says that
    she essentially instantaneously goes from being 4 years old to being 8
    years old during the essentially instantaneous time in his life it takes
    him to stop. And he also says that their distance apart essentially instantaneously increases from 3.464 lightyears to 6.928 lightyears
    while he is doing his essentially instantaneous stopping.

    Keep in mind that when the moving twin stops, both twins will agree
    on how far apart they are. During the deceleration the moving twin
    will observe the apparent expansion of the universe along the axis
    of travel, and what while moving appeared to be 3.464 light years
    will expand to 6.928 light years.

    Something to keep in mind is that neither twin can see the other at
    what each considers "now". They only see the other on their own
    past light cone. So while the moving twin is stopping, he will NOT
    see his twin back on earth suddenly aging. This is because what
    he sees is not the instantaneous state of the earth, but an image
    conveyed by light. Instead he will see her as she was about 6.928
    years earlier. Thus what he sees is a much younger twin, only
    about a year older than when he left earth. It is on the trip back
    to earth that he sees her age rapidly as he passes the light
    traveling outbound from earth.

    Rich L.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Tue Mar 15 18:57:00 2022
    I made a careless mistake in my previous post. Here is that post, down
    to where my mistake occurred:

    On 3/15/22 2:36 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:

    Suppose the two twins have just been born when the traveling twin starts
    his trip. So they are each zero years old then. If the traveling twin
    (he) travels for 4 years of his time, he will be 4 yours old when he
    stops. (His age when he stops is an EVENT that all observers must agree about, and so she also agrees that he is 4 years old when he stops. He
    says he has traveled (0.866)(4) = 3.464 lightyears away from his twin
    (her) then. She says he traveled 8 years of her time ... i.e., she says
    she is 8 years old when he stops. She says he is (0.866)(8) = 6.928 lightyears away when he stops.

    After he stops, she says that he remains 6.928 lightyears away from her
    after that. And she says they age at the same rate after he stops. He
    says that, during his essentially instantaneous stopping time, his age essentially doesn't change during his stopping. She agrees with that.

    The above is all correct. But here is the sentence where I made the
    careless error:

    But he says that during his essentially instantaneous stopping, SHE essentially instantaneously gets older by 4 years ... i.e., he says that
    she essentially instantaneously goes from being 4 years old to being 8
    years old during the essentially instantaneous time in his life it takes
    him to stop.

    According to him, her age right before he stops is 2 years old, not 4
    years old as I said above. Immediately after he stops, they both agree
    about their respective ages. He says she is now 8 years old, so he says
    her age increases by 6 years during his essentially instantaneous
    stopping, not by 4 years as I stated in my previous post.

    I should also have pointed out that each of the twins, during his
    outbound trip, are entitled to use the famous time dilation equation for inertial observers: That equation says that any inertial observer will conclude that a person moving at speed "v" with respect to them is
    ageing at a rate gamma times slower than they are, where

    gamma = 1 / sqrt { 1 / (1 - v * v) },

    where the asterisk indicates multiplication. For v = 0.866, gamma =
    2.0. So on the outbound trip, each twin says the other twin is ageing
    half as fast as their own rate of ageing. So right before he stops, she
    says he is 4 and she is 8, but he says he is 4 and she is 2. And
    immediately after he stops, they both agree that he is 4 and she is 8.
    So he says she essentially instantaneously gets 6 years older during his essentially instantaneous stopping.

    There is an equation that I derived long ago that makes it easy to
    calculate how her age changes (according to him) whenever he essentially instantaneously changes his velocity. I call it the "delta_CADO" equation:

    delta_CADO = -L * delta_v,

    where L is their distance apart, according to her, and

    delta_v = v2 - v1,

    where v1 is his velocity before the change, and v2 is his velocity after
    the change (with positive v being taken as the velocity when they are
    moving apart).

    So in this example,

    L = 6.928 lightyears

    v1 = 0.866 ly/y

    v2 = 0.0 ly/y,

    and so

    delta_v = -0.866

    and

    delta_CADO = -6.928 * (-0.866) = 6.0 years.

    We didn't need this equation to get the answer in the above particular scenario, because his new velocity was zero, which makes things
    especially easy. But when the two velocities are completely general,
    it's necessary to either use the delta-CADO equation, or else do it
    graphically with a Minkowski diagram, drawing lines of simultaneity.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Luigi Fortunati@21:1/5 to All on Wed Mar 16 07:22:52 2022
    Mike Fontenot martedì 15/03/2022 alle ore 19:57:00 ha scritto:
    I made a careless mistake in my previous post. Here is that post, down to where my mistake occurred:

    On 3/15/22 2:36 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:

    Suppose the two twins have just been born when the traveling twin starts
    his trip. So they are each zero years old then. If the traveling twin
    (he) travels for 4 years of his time, he will be 4 yours old when he
    stops. (His age when he stops is an EVENT that all observers must agree
    about, and so she also agrees that he is 4 years old when he stops. He
    says he has traveled (0.866)(4) = 3.464 lightyears away from his twin
    (her) then. She says he traveled 8 years of her time ... i.e., she says
    she is 8 years old when he stops. She says he is (0.866)(8) = 6.928
    lightyears away when he stops.

    After he stops, she says that he remains 6.928 lightyears away from her
    after that. And she says they age at the same rate after he stops. He
    says that, during his essentially instantaneous stopping time, his age
    essentially doesn't change during his stopping. She agrees with that.

    The above is all correct. But here is the sentence where I made the careless error:

    But he says that during his essentially instantaneous stopping, SHE
    essentially instantaneously gets older by 4 years ... i.e., he says that
    she essentially instantaneously goes from being 4 years old to being 8
    years old during the essentially instantaneous time in his life it takes
    him to stop.

    According to him, her age right before he stops is 2 years old, not 4 years old as I said above. Immediately after he stops, they both agree about their respective ages. He says she is now 8 years old, so he says her age increases by 6 years during
    his essentially instantaneous stopping, not by 4 years as I stated in my previous post.

    I should also have pointed out that each of the twins, during his outbound trip, are entitled to use the famous time dilation equation for inertial observers: That equation says that any inertial observer will conclude that a person moving at speed "v"
    with respect to them is ageing at a rate gamma times slower than they are, where

    gamma = 1 / sqrt { 1 / (1 - v * v) },

    where the asterisk indicates multiplication. For v = 0.866, gamma = 2.0. So on the outbound trip, each twin says the other twin is ageing half as fast as their own rate of ageing. So right before he stops, she says he is 4 and she is 8, but he says
    he is 4 and she is 2. And immediately after he stops, they both agree that he is 4 and she is 8. So he says she essentially instantaneously gets 6 years older during his essentially instantaneous stopping.

    Perfect, I was going to report this discrepancy between instant aging of
    4 instead of 6 years, now I absolutely agree with everything you have
    written.

    But you didn't answer my question about the Earth's revolutions around
    the Sun.

    Since I want my question to be clear, I express myself with numbers and
    dates.

    The traveling twin leaves on January 1, 2022 and keeps his telescope continuously pointed at the receding solar system at speed v = 0.866c,
    so that he can count how many revolutions the Earth makes around the
    Sun.

    Obviously, the turns seen on the telescope will take place much slower
    than one for each year, both for the finite speed of the light (which,
    due to the recession, takes more and more time to get to the spaceship
    from the solar system) and for the time dilation

    And all this greatly complicates the calculations.

    This is why I ask: is it possible to calculate how many turns the
    traveler twin will have * seen * make from the Earth around the Sun on
    the spacecraft's telescope, after its 4-year journey, before starting to
    brake?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Richard Livingston on Wed Mar 16 10:47:04 2022
    On 3/15/22 7:55 AM, Richard Livingston wrote:

    Keep in mind that when the moving twin stops, both twins will agree
    on how far apart they are. During the deceleration the moving twin
    will observe the apparent expansion of the universe along the axis
    of travel, and what while moving appeared to be 3.464 light years
    will expand to 6.928 light years.


    That's true. But of the two effects (spatial and temporal), I think
    what special relativity has to say about time is more interesting than
    what it says about space (and distance).

    The best example of that is the case of "negative ageing": if the
    distant traveling twin (he) suddenly accelerates in the direction AWAY
    from the home twin (her), he will conclude that she suddenly gets
    YOUNGER during his velocity change. That result drives a lot of people (including many physicists) crazy! Some physicists maintain that the conclusions of the traveler during those occurrences must be ruled inadmissible. But the negative ageing can't logically be ignored, or disallowed, for the following reason: the traveler can do two
    back-to-back instantaneous velocity reversals, which, taken together,
    just cancel out. So we can't allow one of those velocity reversals, but disallow the other.

    For example, take the case where he is originally moving away from her
    at speed

    v = V1 = +V,

    where V is some positive number. And let L be their distance apart
    (according to her) at some instant. Then, at that instant, he suddenly
    changes his velocity to

    v = V2 = -V.

    So

    delta_v_1 = V2 - V1 = (-V) - V = - 2 * V.

    And

    delta_age_1 = -L * delta_v_1 = -L * (-2 * V) = 2 * L * V.

    So he concludes that her age has instantaneously increased by (2 * L * V).

    But suppose he IMMEDIATELY decides to reverse course again. He will
    then conclude that her age has instantaneously DECREASED by (2 * L * V).
    I.e.,

    delta_v_2 = V - (-V) = V + V = 2 * V.

    and

    delta_age_2 = -L * delta_v_2 = -L * (2 * V) = -2 * L * V.

    So he concludes that her age has instantaneously decreased by (2 * L * V).

    So that gets her age (according to him) right back to where it was
    before he did any accelerating ... everything is as if he had done NO accelerating at all. But that means that we CANNOT say that
    instantaneous age INCREASES are OK, but that instantaneous age DECREASES
    are NOT OK. You can't allow one but disallow the other.


    And Richard Livingston continues:

    Something to keep in mind is that neither twin can see the other at
    what each considers "now". They only see the other on their own
    past light cone. So while the moving twin is stopping, he will NOT
    see his twin back on earth suddenly aging. This is because what
    he sees is not the instantaneous state of the earth, but an image
    conveyed by light. Instead he will see her as she was about 6.928
    years earlier. Thus what he sees is a much younger twin, only
    about a year older than when he left earth. It is on the trip back
    to earth that he sees her age rapidly as he passes the light
    traveling outbound from earth.


    That's all true. But I am not interested in what TV images he receives
    from her ... those just tell him what she looked like in the past, and
    how old she was in the past. Instead, I am interested in what he
    DEDUCES about her CURRENT age at any given instant in his life, using
    the laws of special relativity. I.e., I'm interested in his "NOW"
    instant ... what does he say her age is "RIGHT NOW", at some instant in
    his life. I'm purely interested in what he says about "simultaneity at
    a distance".

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Sylvia Else@21:1/5 to Luigi Fortunati on Wed Mar 16 10:46:16 2022
    On 15-Mar-22 6:08 am, Luigi Fortunati wrote:
    The traveling twin starts and travels for 4 years at speed v = 0.866c
    and then brakes, as seen in the animation
    https://www.geogebra.org/m/jzc4amud

    Calculate the Earth-spaceship distance, before and after braking (in
    the spaceship reference).

    Calculate how many turns the Earth has made around the sun, before and
    after braking (in the spaceship reference).

    Are they identical, mirror, or fraternal twins. If identical, are they conjoined? How would the experiment go for the latter case?

    Sylvia.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Livingston@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Thu Mar 17 15:14:51 2022
    On Wednesday, March 16, 2022 at 12:47:08 PM UTC-5, Mike Fontenot wrote:

    ...
    That's all true. But I am not interested in what TV images he receives
    from her ... those just tell him what she looked like in the past, and
    how old she was in the past. Instead, I am interested in what he
    DEDUCES about her CURRENT age at any given instant in his life, using
    the laws of special relativity. I.e., I'm interested in his "NOW"
    instant ... what does he say her age is "RIGHT NOW", at some instant in
    his life. I'm purely interested in what he says about "simultaneity at
    a distance".

    Simultaneity at a distance is not observable. In our everyday experience
    we actually experience the world on our past light cone and think of that
    as "now". This a misconception. The "now" that Einstein defines with
    his clock synchronization procedure is a useful concept for coordinates,
    but as you are realizing, at any given event in space-time there is no
    unique "now", it is highly observer dependent (i.e. depends on the
    observers state of motion). I suggest that the only reality is on the
    past light cone. That is something that all observers can agree on.
    All observers will agree on WHAT is on the light cone and on the sequence
    of events on the light cone (at least in a given direction), but may disagree on when any event is on the light cone.

    In particular, no matter what you do with direct observation, you will never observe a clock going backwards or a person aging backwards. At most
    you may CALCULATE that a clock on your "now" axis has gone backwards
    due to your acceleration, but you will never be able to directly observe such
    a thing. And I would argue that such a calculation is meaningless.

    Proof of this is two events separated in space and occurring "simultaneously" in some reference frame. The observer in that frame directly observing these events from some time in the future says they occurred simultaneously at
    {some time in the past}. A moving observer at that same place and time as
    the first observer, will also see the two events occurring at the same time,
    no matter how fast they are traveling. It is only when they calculate their "now" times that the paradox of time appears.

    This is why I think it is a mistake in quantum mechanics to talk about the instantaneous collapse of the wave function CAUSED BY a measurement
    event. There cannot be a consistent causal explanation directly linking
    two events that are outside the light cone.

    Rich L.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Luigi Fortunati on Thu Mar 17 15:26:10 2022
    On 3/16/22 1:22 AM, Luigi Fortunati wrote:

    This is why I ask: is it possible to calculate how many turns the
    traveler twin will have * seen * make from the Earth around the Sun on
    the spacecraft's telescope, after its 4-year journey, before starting to brake?


    Yes. I've already shown how the traveling twin (he) can determine the
    current age of the home twin (her) at any instant in his life. And, if
    you know what her mom says the position of the earth in its orbit around
    the sun was when her daughter (the home twin) was born, then that
    establishes a one-to-one correspondence between the home twin's age and
    the position of the earth in its orbit about the sun, and the number of complete orbits it has made since she was born. So that allows the
    traveling twin to determine the position of the earth in its orbit, and
    the number of completed orbits since the home twin was born, at each
    each instant in the life of the traveler (he), according to him. But
    I'm not at all interested in that ... I just want to know what he
    concludes about her current age at each instant of his life.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Phillip Helbig (undress to reply@21:1/5 to Richard Livingston on Thu Mar 17 15:26:56 2022
    In article <d2b386bb-a22a-4cfa-8f07-3a65e9ab76bdn@googlegroups.com>,
    Richard Livingston <richalivingston@gmail.com> writes:

    That's all true. But I am not interested in what TV images he receives
    from her ... those just tell him what she looked like in the past, and
    how old she was in the past. Instead, I am interested in what he
    DEDUCES about her CURRENT age at any given instant in his life, using
    the laws of special relativity. I.e., I'm interested in his "NOW"
    instant ... what does he say her age is "RIGHT NOW", at some instant in
    his life. I'm purely interested in what he says about "simultaneity at
    a distance".

    Simultaneity at a distance is not observable.

    In his most recent book*, Carlo Rovelli summarizes it like this:
    Galilean relativity expresses the idea that the concept of being in the
    same place at different times is ill-defined (relative to what?), while
    Special Relativity expresses the idea that the concept of happening at
    the same time in different places is equally ill-defined.

    Does anyone disagree?

    Considering that one recovers non-relativistic physics in the limit that
    the speed of light goes to infinity, is it fair to say that the finite
    speed of light is the SOLE reason for differences between
    non-relativistic and relativistic physics?

    __
    * _General Relativity: The Essentials_, by Carlo Rovelli (Cambridge
    University Press), 2021. Pp. 180, 23 =D7 15.5 cm. Price =A314.99
    (paperback, ISBN 978 1 00 9013697).

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Stefan Ram@21:1/5 to Richard Livingston on Fri Mar 18 14:27:16 2022
    Richard Livingston <richalivingston@gmail.com> writes:
    Simultaneity at a distance is not observable.

    In an inertial system: Place a detector D midway between A
    and B (using a yardstick). I assume that A, B and D are at
    rest. Generate two signals at A and B. If they arrive at D
    at the same time, they were sent at A and B at the same time.
    This would be a kind of observation, albeit delayed.

    In our everyday experience
    we actually experience the world on our past light cone and think of that
    as "now". This a misconception.

    For /everyday applications/ it does /not/ seem to be
    a misconception, and when the difference between past
    light cone surface and "now" starts to matter, it's
    not an "everyday experience" anymore.

    I suggest that the only reality is on the
    past light cone. That is something that all observers can agree on.

    The everyday reality consists of the things I can interact
    with, like an automated teller machine (ATM). To get this
    type of reality, the "now", in everyday life, needs to be
    extended somewhat to an extended period of time like "today".
    It cannot be only infinitesimally short, like a point of time.

    This is the highest degree of reality: Something is very
    real when one can interact with it, i.e., observe it /and/
    affect it. Causality implies:

    Systems of the past only have a semi-reality:
    You can sometimes observe them, but not affect them.
    For example, the Boston Tea Party. Also, systems of
    the past are only inferred from records, so it is never
    completely sure whether they even existed at all.

    Systems of the future only have a semi-reality:
    You can sometimes affect them, but not observe them.
    For example, the Earth of the year 2023. Also, one
    cannot be completely sure whether there will be such
    an Earth.

    This is why I think it is a mistake in quantum mechanics to talk about the >instantaneous collapse of the wave function CAUSED BY a measurement
    event. There cannot be a consistent causal explanation directly linking
    two events that are outside the light cone.

    When we say "nothing can travel faster than light", this is
    actually not quite correct. An imagined point can travel faster
    than light. If I make a spot on the surface of the moon with
    a laser beam, the spot can move there faster than light.

    It is /energy-impulse transports/, which cannot move faster
    than light (and therefore also information transports).

    The collapse of an imagined function can be imagined in an
    inertial frame quite as "everywhere at the same time",
    as long as no energy-impulse is transported with superluminal
    speed by this collapse.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Tom Roberts@21:1/5 to Stefan Ram on Sat Mar 19 11:27:34 2022
    On 3/18/22 4:27 PM, Stefan Ram wrote:
    Richard Livingston <richalivingston@gmail.com> writes:
    Simultaneity at a distance is not observable.

    In an inertial system: Place a detector D midway between A and B
    (using a yardstick). I assume that A, B and D are at rest. Generate
    two signals at A and B. If they arrive at D at the same time, they
    were sent at A and B at the same time. This would be a kind of
    observation, albeit delayed.

    That is not observing simultaneity at A and B, it is observing
    simultaneity at D. From that observation and the setup and the inertial
    frame, we can INFER that the signals from A and B were sent at the same
    time IN THAT INERTIAL FRAME. Inference is not observation.

    Observation implies a physical quantity is being observed. Simultaneity
    at different spatial points is not any kind of physical quantity, it is
    a CONVENTION based on the time coordinate of a particular inertial
    frame; such coordinate-dependent quantities cannot possibly be physical quantities.

    [...]

    Attempting to apply modern physical theories to our everyday experience
    is hopeless, because there are too many approximations involved.

    Similarly, attempting to discuss "collapse of the wave function" in
    terms of simultaneity and SR is also hopeless, because such "collapse"
    is not observable (one can observe the system transitioning between
    states, but not any "collapse").

    A major lesson of modern physics is to discuss only measurable
    (observable) quantities [#]. Both "everyday lives" and "wavefunction
    collapse" violate that dictum (in very different ways).

    [#] Interestingly, this applies to both QM and GR (for
    very different reasons).

    Tom Roberts

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Tom Roberts on Sun Mar 20 10:44:29 2022
    On 3/19/22 12:27 PM, Tom Roberts wrote:

    Observation implies a physical quantity is being observed. Simultaneity
    at different spatial points is not any kind of physical quantity, it is
    a CONVENTION based on the time coordinate of a particular inertial
    frame


    Tom, what is your "take" on the use of an array of clocks, stationary in
    some inertial frame, that have been synchronized using only the
    assumption that the speed of light is equal to the universal constant
    "c" in that frame. Each of those clocks is attended by a human "helper
    friend" (HF), who can observe his immediate local surroundings. Another particular observer (whom I'll refer to as "he"), also stationary in
    that inertial frame, wants to know (when his watch shows time tau) the
    current reading on a particular distant clock which is NOT stationary
    with respect to that array of clocks. It seems reasonable that he is
    entitled to say that the current reading on that distant clock is what
    the HF, who happens to be colocated with that distant clock at the
    instant when the HF's clock reads tau, directly observes it to be.
    Doesn't that convey a sense of "meaningfulness", to the observers who
    are stationary in that frame? I think Einstein thought it does.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Livingston@21:1/5 to Stefan Ram on Sun Mar 20 10:49:12 2022
    On Friday, March 18, 2022 at 4:27:19 PM UTC-5, Stefan Ram wrote:
    Richard Livingston <richali...@gmail.com> writes:
    Simultaneity at a distance is not observable.
    In an inertial system: Place a detector D midway between A
    and B (using a yardstick). I assume that A, B and D are at
    rest. Generate two signals at A and B. If they arrive at D
    at the same time, they were sent at A and B at the same time.
    This would be a kind of observation, albeit delayed.

    Delayed is the key word. You cannot observe "now" now, you
    can only observe it when it becomes on your past light cone.

    ...

    This is the highest degree of reality: Something is very
    real when one can interact with it, i.e., observe it /and/
    affect it. Causality implies:

    Only events on the past light cone can affect you. Only
    events on your future light cone can be affected by you
    at this moment. Events inside your future light cone can
    be affected in your future.


    Systems of the past only have a semi-reality:
    You can sometimes observe them, but not affect them.
    For example, the Boston Tea Party. Also, systems of
    the past are only inferred from records, so it is never
    completely sure whether they even existed at all.

    Events in the past, to the extent they are recorded or
    (accurately) remembered are something that everyone
    can agree on. That is as close to reality as we will
    ever get.


    ...
    The collapse of an imagined function can be imagined in an
    inertial frame quite as "everywhere at the same time",
    as long as no energy-impulse is transported with superluminal
    speed by this collapse.

    I agree wrt a mathematical function as it applies to any single
    observer. Yet the wave function does represent something
    that is real, imperfectly. I'm not saying the wave function is
    real or that it is exactly something real, but that it somehow
    does capture some aspect of reality. The question is exactly
    what of the wave function is real and what is a mathematical
    fiction, or represents various alternate possibilities. I am
    coming to the conclusion it would be better to call it a
    possibility function rather than a probability function.

    Rich L.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Stefan Ram@21:1/5 to Tom Roberts on Sun Mar 20 10:50:48 2022
    Tom Roberts <tjroberts137@sbcglobal.net> writes:
    A major lesson of modern physics is to discuss only measurable
    (observable) quantities

    In quantum theory, the comprehensive framework theory of
    physics, the state of a system plays the central role.
    This state is not an observable, but discussed extensively!

    In almost all areas of physics, also outside of quantum
    physics, for example in GR, quantities are modeled by real
    numbers, which are also not observable.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Livingston@21:1/5 to Tom Roberts on Sun Mar 20 11:30:33 2022
    On Saturday, March 19, 2022 at 1:27:38 PM UTC-5, Tom Roberts wrote:
    ...
    A major lesson of modern physics is to discuss only measurable
    (observable) quantities [#]. Both "everyday lives" and "wavefunction collapse" violate that dictum (in very different ways).

    [#] Interestingly, this applies to both QM and GR (for
    very different reasons).

    Tom Roberts

    Tom, I would be very interested in your expanding a bit on how this all applies to GR. -Rich L.

    [[Mod. note -- I too would be interested in what Tom says.

    My take would be that in GR, there is no preferred coordinate system
    and all physical quantities (= those that are measurable, at least in
    a gedanken sense) should be independent of the coordinate system in use.

    Notably:
    * the coordinate "time" of an event, or the difference between the
    coordinate times of two events) is merely a coordinate; it has no
    inherent physical meaning and can be changed arbitrarily by changing
    our coordinate system
    * *proper* time along some (timelike) worldline is measurable (it's
    what an (ideal) clock moving along that worldline would measure),
    can be said to have an inherent physical meaning (as the observable
    result of that measurement), and *doesn't* change when we change
    coordinates
    * similarly, the coordinate position of an object, or the (coordinate)
    distance between two objects, is also a coordinate, has no inherent
    physical meaning, and can be changed arbitrarily by changing our
    coordinate system
    * the *proper* distance along a given path is measurable (at least in
    a gedanken sense: one can imagine laying down a sequence of standard
    rulers end-to-end along the path), and doesn't change when we change
    coordinates;
    * coordinate singularities (and the set of events where they occur)
    have no inherent physical meaning, and a change in coordinates can
    change the set of events where there is a coordinate singularity;
    only singularities in observable quantities like curvature invariants,
    proper times/distances, etc, are physically meaningful
    -- jt]]

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Fri Mar 25 10:57:15 2022
    On 3/20/22 4:44 AM, I (Mike Fontenot) wrote:
    On 3/19/22 12:27 PM, Tom Roberts wrote:

    Observation implies a physical quantity is being observed. Simultaneity
    at different spatial points is not any kind of physical quantity, it is
    a CONVENTION based on the time coordinate of a particular inertial
    frame


    Tom, what is your "take" on the use of an array of clocks, stationary in
    some inertial frame, that have been synchronized using only the
    assumption that the speed of light is equal to the universal constant
    "c" in that frame. Each of those clocks is attended by a human "helper friend" (HF), who can observe his immediate local surroundings. Another particular observer (whom I'll refer to as "he"), also stationary in
    that inertial frame, wants to know (when his watch shows time tau) the current reading on a particular distant clock which is NOT stationary
    with respect to that array of clocks. It seems reasonable that he is entitled to say that the current reading on that distant clock is what
    the HF, who happens to be colocated with that distant clock at the
    instant when the HF's clock reads tau, directly observes it to be.
    Doesn't that convey a sense of "meaningfulness", to the observers who
    are stationary in that frame? I think Einstein thought it does.

    Tom hasn't responded yet. Maybe he will shortly. But while waiting,
    I'd like to add a bit to my above argument.

    I think a sizeable number of physicists DO believe that simultaneity at
    a distance is a meaningless concept, and I've even noticed a trend of
    trying to de-emphasize talking about simultaneity-at-a-distance in
    introductory special relativity courses. But I think that is a big
    mistake. It certainly wasn't Einstein's view, at least for inertial
    observers. (I've seen a quote from Einstein somewhere where he said he
    hardly recognizes his theory when he reads some modern descriptions of
    it.)

    My above question of Tom Roberts was prompted mostly by his use of the
    word "Convention" in describing simultaneity at a distance for an
    inertial observer. To me, the term "Convention" implies that there is
    more than one possible answer to the question "How old is that distant
    person (she), right now", when asked and answered by a particular
    inertial observer. "Convention" implies that one can pick from among
    multiple alternatives, all equally good.

    But I don't believe that is true, given my above description of how an
    array of synchronized clocks (all permanently stationary with respect to
    the given inertial observer) can be set up, creating a common "NOW"
    instant for him and for all of the HF's ("helper friends") co-located
    and co-stationary with the clocks. At any given instant "tau" in the
    life of the given inertial observer, it's clear that there is just a
    single answer to the question "How old is that particular distant person
    (she) right now (at the given time "tau" in the life of the inertial
    observer): it is what the particular HF (he) who happens to be
    momentarily co-located with the distant person (she), says it is, at the instant when he is age "tau". The only way there could be any other
    allowable answer is if the synchronization of the clocks isn't valid,
    and that is impossible if the velocity of light in that inertial
    reference frame is equal to the universal constant "c".

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From jtmpreno@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Sat Mar 26 13:31:39 2022
    On 3/25/2022 3:57 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 3/20/22 4:44 AM, I (Mike Fontenot) wrote:
    On 3/19/22 12:27 PM, Tom Roberts wrote:

    Observation implies a physical quantity is being observed. Simultaneity
    at different spatial points is not any kind of physical quantity, it is
    a CONVENTION based on the time coordinate of a particular inertial
    frame


    Tom, what is your "take" on the use of an array of clocks, stationary in
    some inertial frame, that have been synchronized using only the
    assumption that the speed of light is equal to the universal constant
    "c" in that frame. Each of those clocks is attended by a human "helper
    friend" (HF), who can observe his immediate local surroundings. Another
    particular observer (whom I'll refer to as "he"), also stationary in
    that inertial frame, wants to know (when his watch shows time tau) the
    current reading on a particular distant clock which is NOT stationary
    with respect to that array of clocks. It seems reasonable that he is
    entitled to say that the current reading on that distant clock is what
    the HF, who happens to be colocated with that distant clock at the
    instant when the HF's clock reads tau, directly observes it to be.
    Doesn't that convey a sense of "meaningfulness", to the observers who
    are stationary in that frame? I think Einstein thought it does.

    Tom hasn't responded yet. Maybe he will shortly. But while waiting,
    I'd like to add a bit to my above argument.

    I think a sizeable number of physicists DO believe that simultaneity at
    a distance is a meaningless concept, and I've even noticed a trend of
    trying to de-emphasize talking about simultaneity-at-a-distance in introductory special relativity courses. But I think that is a big
    mistake. It certainly wasn't Einstein's view, at least for inertial observers. (I've seen a quote from Einstein somewhere where he said he hardly recognizes his theory when he reads some modern descriptions of
    it.)

    My above question of Tom Roberts was prompted mostly by his use of the
    word "Convention" in describing simultaneity at a distance for an
    inertial observer. To me, the term "Convention" implies that there is
    more than one possible answer to the question "How old is that distant
    person (she), right now", when asked and answered by a particular
    inertial observer. "Convention" implies that one can pick from among multiple alternatives, all equally good.

    But I don't believe that is true, given my above description of how an
    array of synchronized clocks (all permanently stationary with respect to
    the given inertial observer) can be set up, creating a common "NOW"
    instant for him and for all of the HF's ("helper friends") co-located
    and co-stationary with the clocks. At any given instant "tau" in the
    life of the given inertial observer, it's clear that there is just a
    single answer to the question "How old is that particular distant person (she) right now (at the given time "tau" in the life of the inertial observer): it is what the particular HF (he) who happens to be
    momentarily co-located with the distant person (she), says it is, at the instant when he is age "tau". The only way there could be any other allowable answer is if the synchronization of the clocks isn't valid,
    and that is impossible if the velocity of light in that inertial
    reference frame is equal to the universal constant "c".


    What if the twins (or clocks) were quantum-entangled?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Livingston@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Mon Mar 28 10:36:55 2022
    On Friday, March 25, 2022 at 5:57:18 AM UTC-5, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    ...
    I think a sizeable number of physicists DO believe that simultaneity at
    a distance is a meaningless concept, and I've even noticed a trend of
    trying to de-emphasize talking about simultaneity-at-a-distance in introductory special relativity courses. But I think that is a big
    mistake. It certainly wasn't Einstein's view, at least for inertial observers. (I've seen a quote from Einstein somewhere where he said he
    hardly recognizes his theory when he reads some modern descriptions of
    it.)

    My above question of Tom Roberts was prompted mostly by his use of the
    word "Convention" in describing simultaneity at a distance for an
    inertial observer. To me, the term "Convention" implies that there is
    more than one possible answer to the question "How old is that distant
    person (she), right now", when asked and answered by a particular
    inertial observer. "Convention" implies that one can pick from among
    multiple alternatives, all equally good.

    But I don't believe that is true, given my above description of how an
    array of synchronized clocks (all permanently stationary with respect to
    the given inertial observer) can be set up, creating a common "NOW"
    instant for him and for all of the HF's ("helper friends") co-located
    and co-stationary with the clocks. At any given instant "tau" in the
    life of the given inertial observer, it's clear that there is just a
    single answer to the question "How old is that particular distant person (she) right now (at the given time "tau" in the life of the inertial observer): it is what the particular HF (he) who happens to be
    momentarily co-located with the distant person (she), says it is, at the instant when he is age "tau". The only way there could be any other
    allowable answer is if the synchronization of the clocks isn't valid,
    and that is impossible if the velocity of light in that inertial
    reference frame is equal to the universal constant "c".

    I think I mostly agree with you, but still think that the problem with
    "now" at a distant location is that people take it as something
    real and meaningful, and I think an argument can be made that it
    is not very meaningful.

    What is useful for physics is establishing a coordinate framework
    that allows us to describe physics in a consistent way. For this
    purpose "now" at a distant location makes sense. But our
    mathematics is in a sense all knowing in that we keep track of
    events at all locations and times, before they are able to interact
    with other objects in the future.

    For an individual, however, what is "now" at a distant location is
    not something that has a consistent answer. Two different
    observers at the same event can have very different ideas about
    what is happening "now" someplace else. What is indisputably
    real, however, is what these observers can see on their past
    light cone. All observers at an event will see the same things
    on their past light cones.

    Rich L.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to jtmpreno on Mon Mar 28 10:37:26 2022
    On 3/26/22 2:31 PM, jtmpreno wrote:

    What if the twins (or clocks) were quantum-entangled?

    If we were talking about molecular-size objects or smaller, we'd need to
    use quantum mechanics in the analysis. But we're not.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Richard Livingston on Tue Mar 29 11:19:15 2022
    On 3/28/22 3:36 AM, Richard Livingston wrote:
    On Friday, March 25, 2022 at 5:57:18 AM UTC-5, Mike Fontenot wrote:

    [...] At any given instant "tau" in the
    life of the given inertial observer, it's clear that there is just a
    single answer to the question "How old is that particular distant person
    (she) right now (at the given time "tau" in the life of the inertial
    observer): it is what the particular HF (he) who happens to be
    momentarily co-located with the distant person (she), says it is, at the
    instant when he is age "tau". The only way there could be any other
    allowable answer is if the synchronization of the clocks isn't valid,
    and that is impossible if the velocity of light in that inertial
    reference frame is equal to the universal constant "c".

    I think I mostly agree with you, but still think that the problem with
    "now" at a distant location is that people take it as something
    real and meaningful, and I think an argument can be made that it
    is not very meaningful.


    My argument above is that, IF those clocks are synchronized (according
    to the given observer), then he can't help but conclude that the current
    age of that distant person IS completely meaningful TO HIM. And the
    only way that those clocks AREN'T synchronized according to him, is if
    the velocity of light in his inertial reference frame ISN'T equal to the universal constant "c". But the fundamental assumption of special
    relativity IS that light will be measured in all inertial reference
    frames to have the value "c". Therefore, FOR any given inertial
    observer (he), the current age of a distant person is completely
    meaningful to him.

    But what about a non-inertial observer? In particular, what about a
    given observer who is undergoing a constant acceleration? What does HE
    say the current age of a distant person is? It turns out to be possible
    for such an accelerating observer to rely on an array of clocks and
    associated "helper friends" (HF's) to give him the answer. Unlike in
    the inertial case, those clocks DON'T run at the same rate. But the
    ratio of the rates of those clocks can be CALCULATED by the given
    observer. And if he (and the HF's) are initially stationary and
    unaccelerated, they can start out with synchronized clocks (and ages).
    Then, if they all fire their identical rockets at the same instant, they
    can each CALCULATE the current reading of each of the other clocks, at
    each instant in their lives. The calculations of each of the HF's all
    agree. So, at any instant in their lives during that acceleration, they
    each share the same "NOW" instant with all of the other HF's. That
    means that the given observer (he), at any instant "tau" in his life,
    can obtain the current age "T" of some distant person (her), by asking
    the HF, who happens to be momentarily co-located with her at that NOW
    instant, what her age is then.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Tom Roberts@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Sat Apr 2 06:22:52 2022
    On 3/20/22 5:44 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 3/19/22 12:27 PM, Tom Roberts wrote:
    Observation implies a physical quantity is being observed.
    Simultaneity at different spatial points is not any kind of
    physical quantity, it is a CONVENTION based on the time coordinate
    of a particular inertial frame

    Tom, what is your "take" on the use of an array of clocks,
    stationary in some inertial frame, that have been synchronized using
    only the assumption that the speed of light is equal to the universal constant "c" in that frame. Each of those clocks is attended by a
    human "helper friend" (HF), who can observe his immediate local
    surroundings. Another particular observer (whom I'll refer to as
    "he"), also stationary in that inertial frame, wants to know (when
    his watch shows time tau) the current reading on a particular
    distant clock which is NOT stationary with respect to that array of
    clocks. It seems reasonable that he is entitled to say that the
    current reading on that distant clock is what the HF, who happens to
    be colocated with that distant clock at the instant when the HF's
    clock reads tau, directly observes it to be.

    Sure, one could do that. Though there seems to be little motivation to
    do so.

    The particular observer NEVER knows "the current reading" of that
    distant clock (for any meaning of "current"), he can only learn what it
    was at some time in the past (e.g. at time tau), after the HF transmits
    their result to him. Note that in your scenario the particular observer
    must transmit the value of tau to all HFs well in advance;
    alternatively, each HF could record values whenever the distant clock
    passes by, and they all send those records to the particular observer,
    who can then pick and choose among them, after the fact.

    Doesn't that convey a sense of "meaningfulness", to the observers who
    are stationary in that frame? I think Einstein thought it does.

    You simply implemented the CONVENTION of Einstein synchronization. If
    you synchronized the clocks differently you would get a different
    result. It says nothing at all about other frames.

    Tom Roberts

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Tom Roberts@21:1/5 to Richard Livingston on Sat Apr 2 06:22:52 2022
    On 3/20/22 1:30 PM, Richard Livingston wrote:
    On Saturday, March 19, 2022 at 1:27:38 PM UTC-5, Tom Roberts wrote:
    A major lesson of modern physics is to discuss only measurable
    (observable) quantities [#]. Both "everyday lives" and
    "wavefunction collapse" violate that dictum (in very different
    ways).
    [#] Interestingly, this applies to both QM and GR (for very
    different reasons).

    Tom, I would be very interested in your expanding a bit on how this
    all applies to GR. -Rich L.

    Note that coordinates are arbitrary human constructs, which we use to
    simplify, codify, and quantify our observations and descriptions. Nature clearly uses no coordinates, so the choice of coordinates used to
    describe some natural phenomenon cannot possibly affect that phenomenon.
    That is the importance of coordinate independence in GR (and in all of theoretical physics) -- for a quantity to correspond to some physical phenomenon, it must be independent of coordinates (aka invariant).

    For instance, each and every measurement is a definite value for
    whatever physical phenomenon is being measured, and is inherently
    invariant. So observer A can construct a locally inertial frame and use
    it to measure the kinetic energy of a baseball, and all other observers
    will agree that is the value A measures in that frame, even though they themselves use other frames to measure a different value.

    [This has been called a "coordinate-dependent invariant
    quantity -- the value depends on which coordinates are
    used, but the result is invariant because it is
    inextricably bound to the coordinates used.]

    Take careful note of the wording: kinetic energy is NOT invariant,
    but the kinetic energy of a designated object relative to a specified
    inertial frame is indeed invariant. So observers using other frames can
    make measurements of the designated object, transform them to the
    specified frame, and agree on the value obtained in the specified frame.

    Mod. note -- I too would be interested in what Tom says.
    My take would be that in GR, there is no preferred coordinate system
    and all physical quantities (= those that are measurable, at least in
    a gedanken sense) should be independent of the coordinate system in
    use.

    Yes, "should be" => "are".

    Also beware of "preferred coordinate system", because those words are
    ambiguous -- physicists use that phrase in the sense of a coordinate
    system that appears explicitly in the equations of the dynamics; but in many/most cases there is a particular choice of coordinates relative to
    which the calculations are simplified, and we invariably prefer to use
    them. The invariance of physical quantities ensures we can do so.

    Notably:
    * the coordinate "time" of an event, or the difference between the
    coordinate times of two events) is merely a coordinate; it has no
    inherent physical meaning and can be changed arbitrarily by changing
    our coordinate system
    * *proper* time along some (timelike) worldline is measurable (it's
    what an (ideal) clock moving along that worldline would measure),
    can be said to have an inherent physical meaning (as the observable
    result of that measurement), and *doesn't* change when we change
    coordinates
    * similarly, the coordinate position of an object, or the (coordinate)
    distance between two objects, is also a coordinate, has no inherent
    physical meaning, and can be changed arbitrarily by changing our
    coordinate system
    * the *proper* distance along a given path is measurable (at least in
    a gedanken sense: one can imagine laying down a sequence of standard
    rulers end-to-end along the path), and doesn't change when we change
    coordinates;
    * coordinate singularities (and the set of events where they occur)
    have no inherent physical meaning, and a change in coordinates can
    change the set of events where there is a coordinate singularity;
    only singularities in observable quantities like curvature invariants,
    proper times/distances, etc, are physically meaningful
    Yes to all. The Moderator and I agree, except for details in wording.

    Tom Roberts

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Tom Roberts on Sat Apr 2 10:51:23 2022
    On 4/2/22 12:22 AM, Tom Roberts wrote:
    On 3/20/22 5:44 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:

    Doesn't that convey a sense of "meaningfulness", to the observers who
    are stationary in that frame? I think Einstein thought it does.

    You simply implemented the CONVENTION of Einstein synchronization. If
    you synchronized the clocks differently you would get a different
    result.


    If you synchronized those clocks differently, you would be ignoring the fundamental assumption that special relativity is based on: that the
    speed of light in any inertial frame is always equal to the universal
    constant "c".

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Sat Apr 2 18:36:41 2022
    On 3/29/22 4:19 AM, (I) Mike Fontenot wrote:

    But what about a non-inertial observer? In particular, what about a
    given observer who is undergoing a constant acceleration? What does HE
    say the current age of a distant person is? It turns out to be possible
    for such an accelerating observer to rely on an array of clocks and associated "helper friends" (HF's) to give him the answer. Unlike in
    the inertial case, those clocks DON'T run at the same rate. But the
    ratio of the rates of those clocks can be CALCULATED by the given
    observer. And if he (and the HF's) are initially stationary and unaccelerated, they can start out with synchronized clocks (and ages).
    Then, if they all fire their identical rockets at the same instant, they
    can each CALCULATE the current reading of each of the other clocks, at
    each instant in their lives. The calculations of each of the HF's all
    agree. So, at any instant in their lives during that acceleration, they
    each share the same "NOW" instant with all of the other HF's. That
    means that the given observer (he), at any instant "tau" in his life,
    can obtain the current age "T" of some distant person (her), by asking
    the HF, who happens to be momentarily co-located with her at that NOW instant, what her age is then.


    In the above, I said that the given accelerating observer (he)
    (abbreviated, the "AO"), at each instant of his life, can CALCULATE the
    current reading on each of the HF's clocks. What IS that calculation?

    Let t = 0 be the reading on his clock at the instant that the constant acceleration "A" begins, and let all the HFs' clocks also read zero at
    that instant. Thereafter, he and all of the HFs are accelerating at "A" ls/s/s, and the ratio R of any given HF's clock rate to his (the
    observer's (he) whose conclusions we are seeking) clock rate is

    R(t) = [ 1 +- L A sech^2 (A t) ],

    where L is the constant distance between him and the given HF, and
    sech() is the hyperbolic secant (which is the reciprocal of cosh(), the hyperbolic cosine). The "^2" after the sech indicates the square of the
    sech. The "+-" in the above equation means that the second term is
    ADDED to 1 for the HF's who are LEADING the accelerating observer, and
    the second term is SUBTRACTED from 1 for the HF's who are TRAILING the accelerating observer. For brevity, I'll just take the case where the
    HF of interest is a leading HF.

    The limit of R(t), as "t" goes to zero, is 1 + L A. The limit of R(t),
    as "t" goes to infinity, is 1.0 So R(t) starts out at some positive
    number greater than 1, and then approaches 1.0 as t goes to infinity.
    So eventually, all the clocks essentially tic at the same rate, but
    early in the acceleration, the ratio of the tic rates varies
    significantly with time.

    The current reading of the HF's clock (the "Age Change" or "AC"), when
    the AO's clock reads "tau", is

    AC(tau) = integral, from zero to tau, of { R(t) dt }

    = tau + L tanh( A tau ).

    The above result depends on the fact that

    sech^2(u) = d{tanh(u)} / d{u}.

    As tau goes to zero, AC goes to zero. As tau goes to infinity, AC goes
    to tau + L, which goes to infinity, approaching a slope of 1.0 from above.

    So there you have it. That's the calculation that defines "NOW" for the
    AO and all of the HF's, and makes simultaneity at a distance a
    meaningful concept for them. Simultaneity at a distance is not a choice.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Sun Apr 3 18:13:48 2022
    On 4/2/22 11:36 AM, (I) Mike Fontenot wrote:

    So there you have it. That's the calculation that defines "NOW" for the
    AO and all of the HF's, and makes simultaneity at a distance a
    meaningful concept for them. Simultaneity at a distance is not a choice.


    But what does the above say about the current age of the home twin
    (she), according to the traveling twin (he), for each instant in his
    life on his trip? The answer is that the above equations give the same
    results as the Co-Moving-Inertial-Frames (CMIF) simultaneity method.
    That is very fortuitous, because the CMIF method is relatively easy to
    use. The value of the array of clocks discussed above (which establish
    a "NOW" moment for the accelerating observer that extends throughout all
    space) is that they GUARANTEE that the CMIF results are fully meaningful
    to the traveler, and that the CMIF method is the ONLY correct
    simultaneity method for him. He has no other choice.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Tom Roberts@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Sun Apr 3 22:15:18 2022
    On 4/2/22 12:51 PM, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 4/2/22 12:22 AM, Tom Roberts wrote:
    You simply implemented the CONVENTION of Einstein synchronization.
    If you synchronized the clocks differently you would get a
    different result.

    If you synchronized those clocks differently, you would be ignoring
    the fundamental assumption that special relativity is based on: that
    the speed of light in any inertial frame is always equal to the
    universal constant "c".

    As you say, that assumption of SR applies in any INERTIAL FRAME. But if
    one synchronized those clocks differently, they would not yield the time coordinate of an inertial frame, so the assumptions of SR simply would
    not apply, and can be ignored.

    [Don't ask me why anyone would do that, I'm merely pointing
    out that it is possible. The usual Einstein synchronization
    is used because it simplifies the math. As I said before:
    Don't confuse an ordinary human desire for simplicity
    (laziness) with anything more profound.]

    Tom Roberts

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Tom Roberts@21:1/5 to Richard Livingston on Sun Apr 3 22:15:19 2022
    On 3/20/22 1:30 PM, Richard Livingston wrote:
    On Saturday, March 19, 2022 at 1:27:38 PM UTC-5, Tom Roberts wrote:
    A major lesson of modern physics is to discuss only measurable
    (observable) quantities [#]. Both "everyday lives" and
    "wavefunction collapse" violate that dictum (in very different
    ways).
    [#] Interestingly, this applies to both QM and GR (for very
    different reasons).

    Tom, I would be very interested in your expanding a bit on how this
    all applies to GR. -Rich L.

    Note that coordinates are arbitrary human constructs, which we use to
    simplify, codify, and quantify our observations and descriptions. Nature clearly uses no coordinates, so the choice of coordinates used to
    describe some natural phenomenon cannot possibly affect that phenomenon.
    That is the importance of coordinate independence in GR (and in all of theoretical physics) -- for a quantity to correspond to some physical phenomenon, it must be independent of coordinates (aka invariant).

    For instance, each and every measurement is a definite value for
    whatever physical phenomenon is being measured, and is inherently
    invariant. So observer A can construct a locally inertial frame and use
    it to measure the kinetic energy of a baseball, and all other observers
    will agree that is the value A measures in that frame, even though they themselves use other frames to measure a different value.

    [This has been called a "coordinate-dependent invariant
    quantity -- the value depends on which coordinates are
    used, but the result is invariant because it is
    inextricably bound to the coordinates used.]

    Take careful note of the wording: kinetic energy is NOT invariant,
    but the kinetic energy of a designated object relative to a specified
    inertial frame is indeed invariant. So observers using other frames can
    make measurements of the designated object, transform them to the
    specified frame, and agree on the value obtained in the specified frame.

    Mod. note -- I too would be interested in what Tom says.
    My take would be that in GR, there is no preferred coordinate system
    and all physical quantities (= those that are measurable, at least in
    a gedanken sense) should be independent of the coordinate system in
    use.

    Yes, "should be" => "are".

    Also beware of "preferred coordinate system", because those words are
    ambiguous -- physicists use that phrase in the sense of a coordinate
    system that appears explicitly in the equations of the dynamics; but in many/most cases there is a particular choice of coordinates relative to
    which the calculations are simplified, and we invariably prefer to use
    them. The invariance of physical quantities ensures we can do so.

    Notably:
    * the coordinate "time" of an event, or the difference between the
    coordinate times of two events) is merely a coordinate; it has no
    inherent physical meaning and can be changed arbitrarily by changing
    our coordinate system
    * *proper* time along some (timelike) worldline is measurable (it's
    what an (ideal) clock moving along that worldline would measure),
    can be said to have an inherent physical meaning (as the observable
    result of that measurement), and *doesn't* change when we change
    coordinates
    * similarly, the coordinate position of an object, or the (coordinate)
    distance between two objects, is also a coordinate, has no inherent
    physical meaning, and can be changed arbitrarily by changing our
    coordinate system
    * the *proper* distance along a given path is measurable (at least in
    a gedanken sense: one can imagine laying down a sequence of standard
    rulers end-to-end along the path), and doesn't change when we change
    coordinates;
    * coordinate singularities (and the set of events where they occur)
    have no inherent physical meaning, and a change in coordinates can
    change the set of events where there is a coordinate singularity;
    only singularities in observable quantities like curvature invariants,
    proper times/distances, etc, are physically meaningful
    Yes to all. The Moderator and I agree, except for details in wording.

    Tom Roberts

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Tue Apr 5 20:54:03 2022
    (This is an improved version of a posting that I submitted yesterday
    [4-3-22], but which hasn't shown up yet)

    In 1907, Einstein published a VERY long paper (in several volumes) on
    his "relativity principle". In volume 2, section 18, page 302, titled
    "Space and time in a uniformly accelerated reference frame", he
    investigated how the tic rates compare for two clocks separated by the
    constant distance L, with both clocks undergoing a constant acceleration
    "A". He restricted the analysis to very small accelerations (and very
    small resulting velocities). His result (on page 305) was that the
    leading clock tics at a rate

    R = 1 + L A

    faster than the rear clock. Note that that result agrees with my
    equation, for very small "L" and "A". But he then said:

    "From the fact that the choice of the coordinate origin must not
    affect the relation, one must conclude that, strictly speaking, equation
    (30) should be replaced by the equation R = exp(L A). Nevertheless, we
    shall maintain formula (30)."

    I've never understood that one sentence argument he gave, for replacing
    his linear equation with the exponential equation. But I DID assume he
    was right (because he was rarely wrong), until I tried applying his
    exponential equation to the case of essentially instantaneous velocity
    changes that are useful in twin "paradox" scenarios in special
    relativity. Specifically, I worked a series of examples where the
    separation of the two clocks is always

    L = 7.52 ls (lightseconds)

    and where the final speed (with the initial speed being zero) is always

    v = 0.866 ls/s.

    That speed implies a final "rapidity" of

    theta = atanh(0.866) = 1.317 ls/s.

    ("Rapidity" is a non-linear version of velocity. They have a one-to-one correspondence. In special relativity, velocity can never exceed 1.0
    ls/s in magnitude, but rapidity can have an infinite magnitude. An acceleration of "A" ls/s/s lasting for "t" seconds changes the rapidity
    theta by the product of "A" and "t".)

    So in this case, when we are starting from zero velocity and thus zero rapidity, at the end of the acceleration,

    theta = A tau,

    where tau is the duration of the acceleration (according to the rear
    clock). So, if we know theta and tau, we then know the acceleration:

    A = theta / tau.

    I do a sequence of calculations, each starting at t = 0, with the two
    clocks reading zero, and with zero acceleration for t < 0.

    First, I set the duration tau of the acceleration to 1 second. The
    acceleration then needs to be

    A = theta / tau = 1.317 / 1.0 = 1.317 ls/s/s (that's roughly
    40 g's).

    So for this first case, the tic rate of the leading clock during the one
    second acceleration is

    R = exp( L A ) = exp(9.9034), or about 20000.

    (I picked that weird value of "L" so that this value of "R" for the fist
    case would be a round number, just to make the calculations easier.)

    Since R is constant during the acceleration, the CURRENT reading on the
    leading clock (which I'll denote as AC, for "Age Change") is

    AC = tau R = 2x10sup4 = 20000

    (where 10sup4 means "10 raised to the 4th power").

    I then start over and work a second case, with ten times the
    acceleration (13.17 ls/s/s), but with tau ten times smaller (0.1
    second). That keeps the final rapidity the same as in the first case,
    and the final speed is also 0.866, as before. For the second case,

    AC = 1.02x10sup42.

    So when we made the acceleration an order of magnitude larger, and the
    duration an order of magnitude smaller, the current reading "AC" on the
    leading clock got about 38 orders of magnitude larger.

    Next, I start over again and work a third case, again increasing the acceleration by a factor of 10, and the decreasing the duration by a
    factor of 10, so "A" = 131.7 ls/s/s and tau = 0.01 second. Then, AC =
    1.27x10sup428. So this time, when we increased "A" by a factor of 10,
    and decreased tau by a factor of ten, AC got about 380 orders of
    magnitude larger.

    AC is not approaching a finite limit as tau goes to zero and "A" goes to infinity. In each iteration, the change in AC compared to the previous
    change gets MUCH larger. Clearly, the clock reading is NOT converging
    to a finite limit. It is going to infinity as tau goes to zero.

    We can see this, even without doing the above detailed calculations. Since

    AC = tau exp(L A),

    the tau factor goes to zero LINEARLY as tau goes to zero, but exp(L A)
    goes to infinity EXPONENTIALLY as tau goes to zero, so their product is obviously not going to be finite as tau goes to zero.

    So, for the idealization of an essentially instantaneous velocity
    change, the change of the reading on the leading clock is INFINITE
    during the infinitesimal change of the rear clock. That means that,
    when the traveling twin instantaneously changes his speed from zero to
    0.866 (toward the home twin), the exponential version of the R equation
    says that the home twin's age becomes infinite. But we know that's not
    true, because the home twin is entitled to use the time dilation
    equation for a perpetually-inertial observer, and that equation tells
    her that for a speed of 0.866 ls/s, the traveler's age is always
    increasing half as fast as her age is increasing. So when they are
    reunited, she is twice as old he is, NOT infinitely older than he is, as
    the exponential form of the gravitational time dilation equation claims.
    The time dilation equation for a perpetually-inertial observer is the
    gold standard in special relativity. Therefore the exponential form of
    the gravitational time dilation equation is incorrect.

    The correct gravitational time dilation equation turns out to
    approximately agree with what Einstein used in his "small acceleration" analysis, for very small accelerations, but differs substantially for
    larger accelerations. And the correct gravitational time dilation
    equation agrees with the ages of the twins when they are reunited. It
    also exactly agrees with the CMIF simultaneity method for the traveler's conclusions about the sudden increase in the home twin's age when the
    traveler suddenly changes his velocity. The CMIF method provides a
    practical way to compute the change in the home twin's age when the
    traveler instantaneously changes his velocity. But it is the new
    gravitational time dilation equation, and its array of clocks with a
    common "NOW" moment, that guarantees that the CMIF result is fully
    meaningful to the traveling twin, and that the CMIF method is the ONLY
    correct simultaneity method for the traveling twin.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Tom Roberts@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Tue Apr 5 20:53:33 2022
    On 4/3/22 12:13 PM, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 4/2/22 11:36 AM, (I) Mike Fontenot wrote:
    So there you have it. That's the calculation that defines "NOW"
    for the AO and all of the HF's, and makes simultaneity at a
    distance a meaningful concept for them. Simultaneity at a
    distance is not a choice.

    Yes, simultaneity at a distance is a choice. Your approach is
    outrageously unphysical -- maneuvering the ship causes unphysical
    changes in the "age" ascribed to a distant friend.

    But what does the above say about the current age of the home twin
    (she), according to the traveling twin (he), for each instant in his
    life on his trip? The answer is that the above equations give the
    same results as the Co-Moving-Inertial-Frames (CMIF) simultaneity
    method. That is very fortuitous, because the CMIF method is
    relatively easy to use. The value of the array of clocks discussed
    above (which establish a "NOW" moment for the accelerating observer
    that extends throughout all space) is that they GUARANTEE that the
    CMIF results are fully meaningful to the traveler, and that the CMIF
    method is the ONLY correct simultaneity method for him.

    As I keep pointing out and you keep ignoring, this is outrageously
    unphysical. If the traveling twin maneuvers his spaceship, the "age" he ascribes to a distant friend can change very rapidly. No sensible person
    would believe that local actions he takes can "change" his friend's age.

    He has no other choice.

    Not at all. The traveling twin can recognize that his current time is completely divorced from that of his friend far away. If the age of his
    friend is important to him, he would keep track of his motion relative
    to the ICRF, knowing that regardless of his motion or location, the
    current time of the ICRF can be used to calculate the current age of his
    friend (for all practical purposes his friend on earth is at rest in
    the ICRF). Any sensible astronaut would do that.

    Tom Roberts

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Livingston@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Wed Apr 6 11:22:40 2022
    On Tuesday, April 5, 2022 at 2:54:06 PM UTC-5, Mike Fontenot wrote:

    ... {long derivation related to Ehrenfest Paradox and Rendler Coordinates}

    So, for the idealization of an essentially instantaneous velocity
    change, the change of the reading on the leading clock is INFINITE
    during the infinitesimal change of the rear clock. That means that,
    when the traveling twin instantaneously changes his speed from zero to
    0.866 (toward the home twin), the exponential version of the R equation
    says that the home twin's age becomes infinite. But we know that's not
    true, because the home twin is entitled to use the time dilation
    equation for a perpetually-inertial observer, and that equation tells
    her that for a speed of 0.866 ls/s, the traveler's age is always
    increasing half as fast as her age is increasing. So when they are
    reunited, she is twice as old he is, NOT infinitely older than he is, as
    the exponential form of the gravitational time dilation equation claims.
    The time dilation equation for a perpetually-inertial observer is the
    gold standard in special relativity. Therefore the exponential form of
    the gravitational time dilation equation is incorrect.


    Your calculations are all related to the Ehrenfest Paradox and Rindler Coordinates. What myself and others have been trying to get you
    to understand is that the acceleration of the observer does not actually
    change anything about the distant twin. By your own calculations
    the age of the distant twin can be anything +/- c*d depending on the
    relative state of motion and accelerations. Furthermore, with sufficiently high acceleration the observer cannot "see" the distant twin at all.

    Please note that an inertial observer at the same location as your
    traveling twin, watching everything as the traveling twin accelerates,
    does not see any change in the rest of the universe. All these
    coordinate transformations are entirely observer dependent and
    do not represent anything real for the physics. They only affect the APPEARANCE of the world to that observer. Any attempt to place
    greater significance to these appearances is misguided.

    The correct gravitational time dilation equation turns out to
    approximately agree with what Einstein used in his "small acceleration" analysis, for very small accelerations, but differs substantially for
    larger accelerations. And the correct gravitational time dilation
    equation agrees with the ages of the twins when they are reunited. It
    also exactly agrees with the CMIF simultaneity method for the traveler's conclusions about the sudden increase in the home twin's age when the traveler suddenly changes his velocity. The CMIF method provides a
    practical way to compute the change in the home twin's age when the
    traveler instantaneously changes his velocity. But it is the new gravitational time dilation equation, and its array of clocks with a
    common "NOW" moment, that guarantees that the CMIF result is fully
    meaningful to the traveling twin, and that the CMIF method is the ONLY correct simultaneity method for the traveling twin.

    Again, you should study the Ehrenfest Paradox and Rindler Coordinates.
    You still don't seem to appreciate the true significance (or lack thereof)
    of the calculated "now".

    Rich L.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Richard Livingston on Wed Apr 6 21:04:05 2022
    On 4/6/22 12:22 PM, Richard Livingston wrote:

    Your calculations are all related to the Ehrenfest Paradox and Rindler Coordinates.
    I looked up Ehrenfest Paradox on Wiki, and it says it's about a rotating
    disk. The work I've been doing has nothing to do with a rotating disk.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Livingston@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Thu Apr 7 19:02:15 2022
    On Wednesday, April 6, 2022 at 11:04:08 PM UTC-5, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 4/6/22 12:22 PM, Richard Livingston wrote:

    Your calculations are all related to the Ehrenfest Paradox and Rindler Coordinates.
    I looked up Ehrenfest Paradox on Wiki, and it says it's about a rotating disk. The work I've been doing has nothing to do with a rotating disk.

    Mike,

    Sorry about that. I should have referenced the Bell Spaceship paradox.
    That is a closely related effect for a linearly accelerating reference
    frame that is closer to what you are analyzing.

    Rich L.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Richard Livingston on Fri Apr 8 00:05:52 2022
    On 4/6/22 12:22 PM, Richard Livingston wrote:

    What myself and others have been trying to get you (Mike Fontenot)
    to understand is that the acceleration of the observer does not actually change anything about the distant twin.

    It's not clear what that statement even MEANS. Obviously, the distant
    twin (she) doesn't suddenly feel like she's getting younger. At each
    instant in her life, her brain is in a state that is different from all
    of her other brain states. Nothing can change those states. But the accelerating observer DOES conclude that she instantaneously gets
    younger when he instantaneously changes his velocity in the direction
    away from her. And so, FOR HIM, she ACTUALLY gets younger. All perpetually-inertial observers disagree with him about her getting
    younger when he instantaneously changes his velocity, but they also all disagree among themselves about what her current age is when the
    accelerating observer changes his velocity. And FOR EACH OF THEM, she
    ACTUALLY has the current age they compute. That's just the way special relativity IS ... different observers disagree, they all think they are
    right, and none of them is wrong!

    What is really new, though, in my latest results, is the fact that the accelerating observer can assemble an array of clocks (and attending
    "helper friends" (HF's)), which give him a "NOW" that extends throughout
    all space (analogous to what Einstein did for inertial observers). And
    THAT guarantees that the accelerating observer's conclusions about the
    home twin's age are fully MEANINGFUL to him. His conclusions agree with
    the CMIF simultaneity method, which means that the CMIF simultaneity
    method is the only correct simultaneity method.

    [[Mod. note -- I think you're mistaken in a couple of places:

    1. An accelerating obserer ("he") does not (or to be pedantic, should
    not, if he is doing physics correctly) conclude that the distant twin
    ("she") instantaneously gets younger when he instantaneously changes
    his velocity in the direction away from her. Rather he concludes
    that her age coordinate in inertial reference frame #2 (after his
    velocity change) < her age coordinate in inertial reference frame #1
    (before his velocity change). But these are two DIFFERENT inertial
    reference frames, with DIFFERENT time coordinates. Attributing
    physical meaning to a comparison between DIFFERENT inertial frame's
    time coordinates is no more valid than (say) attributing physical
    meaning to the difference between 2022 (the current year on Earth
    in the Gregorian calendar) and 4720 (the current year on Earth in
    the Chinese calendar). If I install new calendar software on my
    computer, I don't suddenly get 4720-2022 years younger or older for
    any sensible meaning of "younger" or "older". :)

    2. What does it mean to say a time coordinate is "physically meaningful"?
    I would argue that it means that you can write the laws of physics
    in a sensible form in terms of that time coordinate. So, what would
    (say) Newton's 2nd law look like using the CMIF time coordinate of
    an accelerating observer? Ick, not nice at all. Or how about Maxwell's
    equations? Or even something very simple like the radioactive decay
    law
    N_atoms(t) = N_atoms(0) * exp(-lambda*t)
    for a fixed lambda. Again, not nice at all if "t" on the left-hand
    side and "t" on the right-hand-side are the time coordinate of different
    inertial frames.

    The fact that these and other laws of physics don't have a sensible
    form when written in a mixture of different time coordinates (such
    as CMIF times for accelerating observers) is, I would argue, prima
    facie evidence that such a mixture of time coordinates is *not*
    physically meaningful.

    3. You write that "the CMIF simultaneity method is the only correct
    simultaneity method". But this begs the question of how to define
    "correct". There are other ways of doing distant clock synchronization
    which differ from Einstein synchronization (e.g., slow (adiabatic)
    clock transport, which gives a different synchronization result
    for each choice of the inertial reference frame in which the clock
    transport is "slow").

    [That is, suppose we are at (fixed) position A in some inertial
    reference frame F0, and set a (gedanken) ideal clock M to match
    our A clock. Then we transport M at velocity v << c to some
    other (fixed) position B a distance d away in this same inertial
    reference frame F0. This takes a time d/v. Since M's Lorentz
    time Lorentz time dialation factor is quadratic in v (for v << c),
    the accumulated time dialation effect on effect on M's clock
    by the time M arrives at B is linear in v, and hence can be
    made arbitrarily small by choosing v small enough (and waiting
    long enough for M to arrive at B). Then when M (eventually)
    arrives at B, we set B's clock to M's reading.

    This defines the "slow clock transport" clock synchronization
    scheme.

    The interesting -- and slightly counterintuitive -- thing is
    that if we observe this entire process from some other inertial
    reference frame F1 which is moving (along the A-B direction)
    with respect to our original inertial reference frame F0, and
    use F1's definition of "slow motion", then it turns out that
    we'll get a *different* clock synchronization.]

    Can you point to a law of physics which specifically picks out
    Einstein synchronization as "correct" and other synchronizations
    as "incorrect"? If not, what basis do we have for saying that
    one of these is "correct".

    -- jt]]

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Fri Apr 8 19:03:52 2022
    On 4/8/22 1:05 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:

    What is really new, though, in my latest results, is the fact that the accelerating observer can assemble an array of clocks (and attending
    "helper friends" (HF's)), which give him a "NOW" that extends throughout
    all space (analogous to what Einstein did for inertial observers). And
    THAT guarantees that the accelerating observer's conclusions about the
    home twin's age are fully MEANINGFUL to him. His conclusions agree with
    the CMIF simultaneity method, which means that the CMIF simultaneity
    method is the only correct simultaneity method.



    [[Mod. note -- I think you're mistaken in a couple of places [...]:

    I WOULD like to hear your "take" on my arguments here:

    First, consider a perpetually-inertial observer (PIO). Einstein showed
    us how that PIO (he) can construct an array of synchronized clocks that
    are stationary wrt him, extending throughout all of space. The clocks
    have been synchronized by using light signals. The fundamental (and
    really only) assumption that defines special relativity is that, in ANY inertial reference frame, the velocity of light is always equal to the universal constant "c". We can also imagine that, co-located with each
    clock is a "helper friend" (HF), whose age is always the same as the
    PIO's age.

    So, if the PIO wants to know "How old is that distant person (she)
    "right now" (say, when the PIO is age T1), he just needs to know which
    HF is momentarily co-located with her when the HF's age is T1. He can eventually determine that, from messages sent him by all the HF's. He
    has previously told all HF's to report to him all encounters with all
    people, telling him what the encountered person's age was, who it was,
    and what the observing HF's age was then. The PIO reviews all those
    responses, and eventually will find one that tells him that, when that
    HF was T1 years old, he was momentarily co-located with the particular
    distant person the PIO is interested in, and her age was T2.

    Now, here is the important question: Given the above, should the PIO
    regard that age of the distant person (that he has eventually
    determined) to be MEANINGFUL? Many people tell me the answer is NO.
    But I claim that, if the PIO says that, he will effectively be saying
    that he doesn't believe that the speed of light is equal to "c" in his
    inertial frame. And if he doesn't believe that, he doesn't believe in
    special relativity.

    All of the above applies equally well to the array of clocks and
    helper-friends I've described for someone (the "AO") who is initially unaccelerated, but who then undergoes a constant non-zero acceleration
    for some length of time. That AO can also be mutually stationary with
    respect to an array of clocks that establish a "NOW" moment for him,
    extending throughout all space. The previous arguments all apply to the
    AO as well. The only difference is that, if the AO doesn't regard the
    answer he has gotten for the distant person's current age to be
    MEANINGFUL, that doesn't imply that he doesn't believe that the speed of
    light is "c" (he already knows that the speed of light in his frame is
    NOT "c"). If the AO doesn't regard the answer he has gotten for the
    distant person's current age to be MEANINGFUL, that implies that he
    doesn't believe that the equations he has used to calculate the current
    reading on each of the HFs' clocks are correct. If he DOES believe
    those equations are correct, then he MUST conclude that the distant
    person's current age he has determined IS meaningful. I believe those equations are correct. Others may believe they are not correct. I
    think they ARE potentially testable.

    [[Mod. note --
    What do you mean by the word "meaningful"?

    If the AO accelerates, he will assign a different CMIF-time to a given
    (fixed) event (e.g., the explosion of the first hydrogen bomb on Earth),
    and correspondingly assign the label "now @ Earth worldline" to a
    different event along the Earth's worldline.

    But does anything in the universe (other than AO's motion and the
    observations AO makes) change when the AO accelerates? If not, then
    what is the basis for declaring changes in AO-CMIF-time "meaningful"?

    It might be useful to conceptualize the AO and his CMIF definition of
    "now @ Earth worldline" as a "time viewer" than can observe the Earth
    at any point (event) on the Earth's past worldline. Accelerating the AO (changing the AO's velocity with respect to some inertial reference frame)
    then corresponds to turning the control knob on this "time viewer" back
    and forth (and hence moving the AO's "now @ Earth worldline" observation
    point forwards and backwards in time along the Earth's past worldline).
    Do you consider this change in observation point to be "meaningful"
    (beyond its obvious change in what AO himself observes)?

    This change in observation point is certainly not unique -- another accelerating observer AO' will in general ascribe a different observation point. And, this observation point can move superluminally both forwards
    and backwards in time. And, no observation on Earth (apart from asking
    AO to report what he is observing) changes when AO moves his observation
    point.

    To me, this all (very strongly) suggests that the motion of this
    observation point (i.e., AO's CMIF-time definition of "now" at the Earth's position) doesn't deserve to be called "physically meaningful".
    -- jt]]

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Julio Di Egidio@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Sun Apr 10 11:47:48 2022
    On Saturday, 9 April 2022 at 04:03:57 UTC+2, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 4/8/22 1:05 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:

    What is really new, though, in my latest results, is the fact that the accelerating observer can assemble an array of clocks (and attending "helper friends" (HF's)), which give him a "NOW" that extends throughout all space (analogous to what Einstein did for inertial observers). And
    THAT guarantees that the accelerating observer's conclusions about the
    home twin's age are fully MEANINGFUL to him. His conclusions agree with
    the CMIF simultaneity method, which means that the CMIF simultaneity
    method is the only correct simultaneity method.

    [[Mod. note -- I think you're mistaken in a couple of places [...]:

    I WOULD like to hear your "take" on my arguments here:

    (IMO) You are perfectly right: relativity as it is usually presented
    and interpreted is simply inconsistent and arbitrary nonsense unless
    one does fix the notion of *proper time* and what that even means.
    Indeed yes, if I and you synchronize our clocks, and as long as the
    clocks keep working, forever and ever I and you will be reading the
    same exact time at at the same exact moment, aka we age the same
    just like clocks tick the same (amd I think this is already some
    postulate, and if not it should be). The fact that we on the other
    hand move in space-time entails we are not anymore on the same plane
    of simultaneity, it does not and cannot change the synchronization
    of our clocks any more than it does in Galilean physics, just we
    here drift in space-time instead of just space. Proper time is
    just not coordinate time which has rather to do with coordinate
    systems. And if we drop that postulate I am saying, physics indeed
    becomes "disconnected" and plain arbitrary...

    Please look at this diagram to begin with: isn't there already, in it's elementarity indeed, the unescapable answer to all above questions?

    <https://jp-diegidio.github.io/STUDY.Physics.SpecialRelativity/InertialFrames/App/index.html>

    Julio

    [[Mod. note -- When you write
    I and you synchronize our clocks, and as long as the
    clocks keep working, forever and ever I and you will be reading the
    same exact time at at the same exact moment
    that's only true if we follow the same worldline, i.e., if our positions
    are the same at all times. If our positions differ then in general we'll
    see different clock readings when we get back together again -- this was experimentally tested by (among others) the Hafele-Keating experiment
    (1972)
    https://paulba.no/paper/Hafele_Keating.pdf
    -- jt]]

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Sun Apr 10 11:52:23 2022
    On 4/8/22 8:03 PM, the Moderator (JT) wrote:

    What do you mean by the word "meaningful"?


    If I were ever able to take an actual long-term, high-speed space
    voyage, I'm sure I would often wonder what my wife back home was doing
    "right now". I definitely wouldn't believe that she had ceased to exist
    just because we were separated.

    If she exists "right now", then she must be doing something specific
    right now. And that "doing something right now" is associated with a
    certain unique state of her brain right now. And each unique state of
    her brain corresponds to a unique specific time in her life. So I would
    regard her current age during each instant in my life on my trip as
    being completely meaningful to me.

    And if my maneuvering on my trip resulted in my calculating that she was exactly the same age at two widely separated instants in my life, I
    would just say "WOW, isn't that interesting!". I would believe it. It
    would be completely meaningful to me.


    [[Mod. note -- So basically you're saying that what you observe is
    meaningful to you, regardless of whether anything else in the universe
    is affected.
    -- jt]]

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Mon Apr 11 08:00:11 2022
    On 4/10/22 12:52 PM, the Moderator (JT) wrote:

    So basically you're saying that what you observe is
    meaningful to you, regardless of whether anything else in the universe
    is affected.


    If I am an accelerating observer, and if I OBSERVE a TV image of the
    distant person, that tells me what that distant person looked like a
    long time ago. That's not meaningful to me, because I don't know how to determine how much she aged while the message was in transit.

    But if I'm mutually stationary wrt the array of clocks that I have
    previously described, which provides a "NOW" for me extending throughout
    space, that DOES give me a meaningful answer to the question of how old
    she currently is. And by "meaningful", I mean that I REALLY believe
    that she is currently that age. The only way I can be wrong about her
    current age is if my equation for the rate ratio of the two clocks is
    wrong. I'm confident that it is correct. I think it IS experimentally testable.

    I don't understand what you meant in the above, when you said
    "regardless of whether anything else in the universe
    is affected". Although I realize that the way I accelerate affects what
    I conclude about how her age changes, I don't contend that that has ANY
    effect on what other observers (including she herself) conclude about
    her age changes. Different people disagree about simultaneity at a
    distance. That's just the way special relativity is.

    Michael Leon Fontenot

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Tom Roberts@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Mon Apr 11 12:19:47 2022
    On 4/11/22 3:00 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    if I'm mutually stationary wrt the array of clocks that I have
    previously described, which provides a "NOW" for me extending
    throughout space, [...]

    If you are an astronaut in a spaceship that can travel at an appreciable fraction of c, and which you maneuver, then such an array of clocks is impossible -- each such clock must vary its acceleration in concert with
    yours, so the spaceships carrying those clocks must be clairvoyant,
    because they are separated from you by spacelike intervals. Moreover,
    such clocks located sufficiently far away from you will require an
    unphysical acceleration and/or velocity to remain on station; you
    cannot cover the universe with them, only a region "close" to you (how
    close depends on the details of your maneuvering).

    [I suppose you could plan out your trip in exquisite
    detail, and the spaceships carrying the other clocks
    could pre-compute their accelerations to match. But
    anyone who has ever driven a car knows how poorly
    such plans are followed.]

    If you carefully keep track of your acceleration, velocity, and position relative to some coordinates, then you can calculate what "now" means to
    you at a distant location, as you maneuver. As I have pointed out many
    times before, that in general gives nonsensical and unphysical results.

    If you "believe" that your wife back home can grow younger due to your maneuvering, then you will believe anything, which is useless, and is
    certainly not physics.

    Tom Roberts

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Mon Apr 11 12:18:50 2022
    On 4/11/22 2:00 AM, (I) Mike Fontenot wrote:

    If I am an accelerating observer, and if I OBSERVE a TV image of the
    distant person, that tells me what that distant person looked like a
    long time ago. That's not meaningful to me, because I don't know how to determine how much she aged while the message was in transit.


    I need to correct that last sentence. Observing the TV image of the
    distant person WOULD be meaningful to me. ALL observations are
    meaningful, almost by definition. But what I was thinking when I made
    that statement was that, that observation wouldn't help me determine her current age "right now", because I don't know how to determine how much
    she aged while the message was in transit.

    But if I'm mutually stationary wrt the array of clocks that I have
    previously described, which provides a "NOW" for me extending throughout space, that DOES give me a meaningful answer to the question of how old
    she currently is. And by "meaningful", I mean that I REALLY believe
    that she is currently that age. The only way I can be wrong about her current age is if my equation for the rate ratio of the two clocks is
    wrong. I'm confident that it is correct. I think it IS experimentally testable.


    The ability to construct an array of clocks (mutually stationary with
    the accelerating observer) establishes a "NOW" moment for him, and
    answers his question about her current age in a way that is fully
    meaningful. But that hinges on my equations for the rate ratio R(t) and
    the ace change AC(t) being correct.

    The rate ratio equation is

    R(t) = [ 1 +- L A sech^2 (A t) ],

    where L is the constant distance between him and the given HF, and
    sech() is the hyperbolic secant (which is the reciprocal of cosh(), the hyperbolic cosine). The "^2" after the sech indicates the square of the
    sech. The "+-" in the above equation means that the second term is
    ADDED to 1 for the HF's who are LEADING the accelerating observer, and
    the second term is SUBTRACTED from 1 for the HF's who are TRAILING the accelerating observer.

    The limit of R(t), as "t" goes to zero, is 1 + L A. The limit of R(t),
    as "t" goes to infinity, is 1.0 So R(t) starts out at some positive
    number greater than 1, and then approaches 1.0 as t goes to infinity. So eventually, all the clocks essentially tic at the same rate, but early
    in the acceleration, the ratio of the tic rates varies significantly
    with time.

    The current reading of the HF's clock (the "Age Change" or "AC"), when
    the AO's clock reads "tau", is

    AC(tau) = integral, from zero to tau, of { R(t) dt }

    = tau + L tanh( A tau ).

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Tom Roberts on Tue Apr 12 07:21:19 2022
    On 4/11/22 1:19 PM, Tom Roberts wrote:

    If you are an astronaut in a spaceship that can travel at an appreciable fraction of c, and which you maneuver, then such an array of clocks is impossible -- each such clock must vary its acceleration in concert with yours [...]

    No, that's not correct. According to the accelerating observer (the
    AO), whose conclusions we seek, he and each of his "helper friends"
    (HF's) undergo EXACTLY the same (constant) acceleration, as recorded on
    their accelerometers. This is clear by looking at the equivalent
    scenario in the case of a constant gravitational field with no
    accelerations (via the equivalence principle) ... all of those people
    are motionless, unaccelerated, and mutually stationary. And according
    to them, the distance between each of them is also constant. In the acceleration scenario (in the infinite flat spacetime of special
    relativity), perpetually-inertial observers, who are initially
    stationary with respect to the AO and the HF's, WILL conclude that the accelerations of the AO and the various HF's, and their distances apart,
    DO vary with time. But it is not their conclusions that I am interested in.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Tue Apr 12 07:21:19 2022
    On 4/11/22 2:00 AM, (I) Mike Fontenot wrote:

    If I am an accelerating observer, and if I OBSERVE a TV > image of
    the distant person, that tells me what that distant > person looked like
    along time ago. That's not meaningful > to me, because I don't know how
    to determine how much > she aged while the message was in transit.


    I need to correct that last sentence. Observing the TV image of the
    distant person WOULD be meaningful to me. ALL observations are
    meaningful, almost by definition. But what I was thinking when I made
    that statement was that, that observation wouldn't help me determine her current age "right now", because I don't know how to determine how much
    she aged while the message was in transit.

    But if I'm mutually stationary wrt the array of clocks that I > have
    previously described, which provides a "NOW" for >me extending
    throughout space, that DOES give me a >meaningful answer to the question
    of how old
    she currently is. And by "meaningful", I mean that I >REALLY believe
    that she is currently that age. The only >way I can be wrong about her
    current age is if my equation >for the rate ratio of the two clocks is
    wrong. I'm confident >that it is correct. I think it IS experimentally testable.


    The ability to construct an array of clocks (mutually stationary with
    the accelerating observer) establishes a "NOW" moment for him, and
    answers his question about her current age in a way that is fully
    meaningful. But that hinges on my equations for the rate ratio R(t) and
    the age change AC(t) being correct.

    The rate ratio equation is

    R(t) = [ 1 +- L A sech^2 (A t) ],

    where L is the constant distance between him and the given HF, and
    sech() is the hyperbolic secant (which is the reciprocal of cosh(), the hyperbolic cosine). The "^2" after the sech indicates the square of the
    sech. The "+-" in the above equation means that the second term is
    ADDED to 1 for the HF's who are LEADING the accelerating observer, and
    the second term is SUBTRACTED from 1 for the HF's who are TRAILING the accelerating observer.

    The current reading of the HF's clock (the "Age Change" or "AC"), when
    the AO's clock reads "tau", is

    AC(tau) = integral, from zero to tau, of { R(t) dt }

    = tau + L tanh( A tau ).

    If anyone can spot an error in my derivation of those two equations,
    please let me know about it. The derivations are fairly lengthy, but
    are shown completely in the paper that I put on the viXra on-line
    repository:

    https://vixra.org/abs/2201.0015

    Michael Leon Fontenot
    mlfasf@comcast.net

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Tom Roberts@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Tue Apr 12 11:28:54 2022
    On 4/12/22 2:21 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 4/11/22 1:19 PM, Tom Roberts wrote:
    If you are an astronaut in a spaceship that can travel at an
    appreciable fraction of c, and which you maneuver, then such an
    array of clocks is impossible -- each such clock must vary its
    acceleration in concert with yours [...]

    No, that's not correct.

    Yes, it is correct. Finally you say what you are thinking behind the
    scenes, and I can now explain that you are thinking of an inappropriate analogy.

    According to the accelerating observer (the AO), whose conclusions
    we seek, he and each of his "helper friends" (HF's) undergo EXACTLY
    the same (constant) acceleration, as recorded on their
    accelerometers.

    This is wrong. You require the helper friends to remain at the same
    proper distance from the accelerating observer -- i.e. in each
    successive instantaneously co-moving inertial frame (ICIF) those
    distances are constant. That is Born rigid motion, and it is well
    known that HFs lower than the AO must have larger proper accelerations
    than the AO, and HFs above the AO must have smaller proper
    accelerations; there is often a limit below which no HF can possibly
    keep up, so in general the HFs cannot cover the manifold.

    [Note that accelerometers display their proper acceleration.]

    Moreover, whenever the observer maneuvers (changes his proper
    acceleration), all of the HFs must SIMULTANEOUSLY (in the current ICIF)
    make corresponding changes to their proper accelerations -- that
    requires either clairvoyance or detailed pre-planning, because they are separated by spacelike intervals from the AO. As such detailed
    pre-planning cannot hold for a spacefaring astronaut (who will maneuver
    his spacecraft based on current observations), I said that this array
    of HFs is impossible.

    This is clear by looking at the equivalent scenario in the case of a
    constant gravitational field with no accelerations (via the
    equivalence principle) ... all of those people are motionless,
    unaccelerated, and mutually stationary. And according to them, the
    distance between each of them is also constant.

    (I presume you mean a static gravitational field, all
    those people are located at various altitudes with each
    4-velocity parallel to the timelike Killing vector, and
    the field is uniform in that their proper accelerations
    are all equal. I also presume that "all of those people"
    are the AO and all the HFs. Note this is not "equivalent"
    to the above scenario, as I discuss next.)

    This is wrong at several levels.
    1) The HFs are not "motionless" or "mutually stationary" in any of the
    AO's ICIFs; this is not Born rigid motion.
    2) the HFs are not "unaccelerated" -- each has a nonzero proper
    acceleration (even though they have zero coordinate acceleration [#]).
    3) the equivalence principle applies only in a region small enough that
    the curvature of spacetime is negligibly small (compared to measurement accuracy); it CLEARLY does not apply here.
    4) the distances between the HFs and the AO are not "constant" in any
    ICIF -- you are confusing constant coordinate difference [#] with
    constant distance in an ICIF -- the AO and HFs have constant coordinate
    values (and differences) [#], but not constant distances in any of the
    ICIFs (as required by your scenario above).

    [#] Implicitly using coordinates aligned with the static
    gravitational field. These are not the coordinates of any
    of the ICIFs.

    It seems you have implicitly been thinking of this inappropriate analogy
    all along. Relativity is more complicated than that (even in flat
    spacetime).

    In the acceleration scenario (in the infinite flat spacetime of
    special relativity), perpetually-inertial observers, who are
    initially stationary with respect to the AO and the HF's, WILL
    conclude that the accelerations of the AO and the various HF's, and
    their distances apart, DO vary with time.

    But the only way to construct that collection of HFs is for the AO to
    adhere to a detailed, prearranged plan of accelerations, so each HF can pre-compute their own detailed plan of accelerations. The AO cannot
    maneuver to, say, land on a discovered planet or orbit a discovered star.

    But it is not their conclusions that I am interested in.

    But as I keep saying, the conclusions you are interested in are
    nonsensical and unphysical. And the AO + HFs scenario you have in mind
    is either impossible, or requires unacceptably rigid adherence to a pre-computed plan (and even then can be limited in scope).

    Tom Roberts

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Julio Di Egidio@21:1/5 to Julio Di Egidio on Tue Apr 12 15:55:35 2022
    On Sunday, 10 April 2022 at 20:47:52 UTC+2, Julio Di Egidio wrote:
    On Saturday, 9 April 2022 at 04:03:57 UTC+2, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 4/8/22 1:05 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:

    What is really new, though, in my latest results, is the fact that the accelerating observer can assemble an array of clocks (and attending "helper friends" (HF's)), which give him a "NOW" that extends throughout all space (analogous to what Einstein did for inertial observers). And THAT guarantees that the accelerating observer's conclusions about the home twin's age are fully MEANINGFUL to him. His conclusions agree with the CMIF simultaneity method, which means that the CMIF simultaneity method is the only correct simultaneity method.

    [[Mod. note -- I think you're mistaken in a couple of places [...]:

    I WOULD like to hear your "take" on my arguments here:
    (IMO) You are perfectly right: relativity as it is usually presented
    and interpreted is simply inconsistent and arbitrary nonsense unless
    one does fix the notion of *proper time* and what that even means.
    Indeed yes, if I and you synchronize our clocks, and as long as the
    clocks keep working, forever and ever I and you will be reading the
    same exact time at at the same exact moment, aka we age the same
    just like clocks tick the same (amd I think this is already some
    postulate, and if not it should be). The fact that we on the other
    hand move in space-time entails we are not anymore on the same plane
    of simultaneity, it does not and cannot change the synchronization
    of our clocks any more than it does in Galilean physics, just we
    here drift in space-time instead of just space. Proper time is
    just not coordinate time which has rather to do with coordinate
    systems. And if we drop that postulate I am saying, physics indeed
    becomes "disconnected" and plain arbitrary...

    Please look at this diagram to begin with: isn't there already, in it's elementarity indeed, the unescapable answer to all above questions?

    <https://jp-diegidio.github.io/STUDY.Physics.SpecialRelativity/InertialFrames/App/index.html>

    No comments on that? That is the most concrete and immediate alleged
    proof of my point: easy to read, impossible to equivocate upon,
    easy to debunk if that's the case: and should you just call that
    "arbitrary" (how proper time becomes the very relation between
    different frames/observers), then you should tell me what's your
    picture of it and how it even works. And please notice that I clam
    that that is SR, not something else: i.e. I am not proposing an
    alternative theory here, just reading the existing one.

    [[Mod. note -- When you write
    I and you synchronize our clocks, and as long as the
    clocks keep working, forever and ever I and you will be reading the
    same exact time at at the same exact moment
    that's only true if we follow the same worldline, i.e., if our positions
    are the same at all times.

    No, that is universally true (not even limited to inertial frames):
    *locally* I and you experience the one and only universal time, aka
    *proper* time (as do our clocks and everything else).

    If our positions differ then in general we'll
    see different clock readings when we get back together again

    "Drifting" happens in coordinate space-time: with an analogy, If I
    take a trip away from you and later come back, the reading of our
    (spacial) mileage would be different, yet that doesn't mean space
    for me is not the same as space for you... exactly the same in SR,
    just here it's the space-time mileage: to reiterate, an altogether
    different notion than proper time/distance.

    I risk to botch the terminology, but the problem there is essentially
    mixing simultaneity (which is a bunch of operational definitions
    to compute from *within* a frame) with synchronicity (isochronous
    lines and so on), which is simply something else, namely *elapsed
    proper time/distance*.

    -- this was
    experimentally tested by (among others) the Hafele-Keating experiment
    (1972)
    https://paulba.no/paper/Hafele_Keating.pdf

    AFAICT, I am not contradicting the theory, even less any experimental
    result.

    BTW, thanks for the reply, appreciated.

    Julio

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Thu Apr 14 13:32:50 2022
    Tom, you've misunderstood what I'm doing.

    Start with the gravitational scenario, with no acceleration and no
    motion at all. Imagine that there is a high-rise building, with many
    floors. A clock and the "AO" (whose "viewpoint" we are seeking) is
    located on the first floor. A clock and an attending HF is on each of
    the higher floors. The distance between the AO and each of the HF's is constant. They are all motionless and unaccelerated.

    There is initially no gravitational field. And initially all of the
    clocks are synchronized and ticking at the same rate. So initially, the
    rate ratio R, for each HF's clock, is just equal to 1.0.

    But at some instant (say, t = 0), there suddenly appears a constant and
    uniform gravitational field, of strength "g", directed downwards, and
    acting over the entire length of the building. Each person suddenly
    feels exactly the same force per unit mass, trying to pull them
    downwards against the floor. (But they don't move, because they were
    already tethered in that position). They could be constantly standing
    on a bathroom scale, displaying their weight.

    The gravitational time dilation equation says that, according to the AO,
    each HF's clock suddenly starts ticking faster than the AO's clock, by
    the rate ratio

    R(t) = [ 1 + L g sech^2 (g t) ],

    where "L" is the distance between the AO and that particular HF. And, according to the AO, the change in age (AC) of each HF (relative to his
    age when the field suddenly appeared), is

    AC(tau) = integral, from zero to tau, of { R(t) dt }

    = tau + L tanh( g tau ).

    So that's the outcome of the gravitational scenario.

    We now use the equivalence principle (EP) to convert the above
    gravitational scenario to the EQUIVALENT scenario with the constant and
    uniform GRAVITATIONAL FIELD acting on the AO and each HF replaced by a
    constant and uniform ACCELERATION acting on the AO and each HF.
    Everything else stays exactly the same, except the gravitational field
    is replaced by an acceleration.

    Just as in the gravitational scenario, each person suddenly feels
    exactly the same force per unit mass, trying to pull them against the
    floor. (But they don't move, because they were already tethered in that position). They could be constantly standing on a bathroom scale,
    displaying their weight. That serves as an accelerometer.

    The equivalence principle says that EVERYTHING stays the same as in the gravitational scenario, except that the parameter "g" just gets replaced
    by the parameter "A" in the equations, with each having the same
    numerical value. So we still have the same equation for R and for AC as
    we had above, with "g" replaced by "A", with equal numerical values. The
    fact that "L" and "g" don't vary with time in the gravitational scenario
    means that "L" and "A" don't vary with time in the acceleration scenario either.

    Mike Fontenot

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Thu Apr 14 21:25:30 2022
    Tom, you've badly misunderstood what I'm doing.

    Start with the gravitational scenario, with no acceleration and no
    motion at all. Imagine that there is a high-rise building, with many
    floors. A clock and the "AO" (whose "viewpoint" we are seeking) is
    located on the first floor. A clock and an attending HF is on each of
    the higher floors. The distance between the AO and each of the HF's is constant. They are all motionless and unaccelerated.

    There is initially no gravitational field. And initially all of the
    clocks are synchronized and ticking at the same rate. So initially, the
    rate ratio R, for each HF's clock, is just equal to 1.0.

    But at some instant (say, t = 0), there suddenly appears a constant and
    uniform gravitational field, of strength "g", directed downwards, and
    acting over the entire length of the building. Each person suddenly
    feels exactly the same force per unit mass, trying to pull them
    downwards against the floor. (But they don't move, because they were
    already tethered in that position). They could be constantly standing
    on a bathroom scale, displaying their weight.

    The gravitational time dilation equation says that, according to the AO,
    each HF's clock suddenly starts ticking faster than the AO's clock, by
    the rate ratio

    R(t) = [ 1 + L g sech^2 (g t) ],

    where "L" is the distance between the AO and that particular HF. And, according to the AO, the change in age (AC) of each HF (relative to his
    age when the field suddenly appeared), is

    AC(tau) = integral, from zero to tau, of { R(t) dt }

    = tau + L tanh( g tau ).

    So that's the outcome of the gravitational scenario.

    We now use the equivalence principle (EP) to convert the above
    gravitational scenario to the EQUIVALENT scenario with the constant and
    uniform GRAVITATIONAL FIELD acting on the AO and each HF replaced by a
    constant and uniform ACCELERATION acting on the AO and each HF.
    Everything else stays exactly the same, except the gravitational field
    is replaced by an acceleration.

    Just as in the gravitational scenario, each person suddenly feels
    exactly the same force per unit mass, trying to pull them against the
    floor. (But they don't move, because they were already tethered in that position). They could be constantly standing on a bathroom scale,
    displaying their weight. That serves as an accelerometer.

    The equivalence principle says that EVERYTHING stays the same as in the gravitational scenario, except that the parameter "g" just gets replaced
    by the parameter "A" in the equations, with each having the same
    numerical value. So we still have the same equation for R and for AC as
    we had above, with "g" replaced by "A", with equal numerical values.
    The fact that "L" and "g" don't vary with time in the gravitational
    scenario means that "L" and "A" don't vary with time in the acceleration scenario either.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Livingston@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Fri Apr 15 11:11:54 2022
    On Thursday, April 14, 2022 at 11:25:34 PM UTC-5, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    ...
    But at some instant (say, t = 0), there suddenly appears a constant and uniform gravitational field, of strength "g", directed downwards, and
    acting over the entire length of the building. Each person suddenly
    feels exactly the same force per unit mass, trying to pull them
    downwards against the floor. (But they don't move, because they were
    already tethered in that position). They could be constantly standing
    on a bathroom scale, displaying their weight.

    If you do this you will find that the distance to each helper observer no longer remains constant. If you force the distances to remain constant
    then the helper observers cannot have the same acceleration. Please
    study the "Spaceship Paradox" and Rindler coordinates. You are
    making an assumption that is not correct.

    Rich L.

    [[Mod. note -- Bell's "spaceship paradox" is indeed highly relevant
    here. The Wikipedia article
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bell%27s_spaceship_paradox
    is a nice introduction.

    In this context, when trying to understand the meaning and implications
    of the phrase "there suddenly appears", it's important to ask "suddenly
    in which inertial reference frame?", and to think about whether things
    would still happen "suddenly" in other inertial reference frames.
    -- jt]]

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Fri Apr 15 16:06:21 2022
    You (Richard Livingston and moderator JT) are both confusing the
    conclusions of the people who are undergoing acceleration with the
    conclusions of people who are perpetually-inertial and who are observing
    the people who are accelerating. The perpetually-inertial people DO
    conclude that the distance between the accelerating people decreases
    when they accelerate, but the people who are accelerating don't agree.


    Mike Fontenot

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Tom Roberts@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Fri Apr 15 23:57:20 2022
    On 4/14/22 11:25 PM, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    Tom, you've misunderstood what I'm doing.

    No, I don't think I have. But you have misunderstood basic relativity,
    and have misunderstood when the equivalence principle applies, and when
    it doesn't. See my recent post about this.

    [... completely new scenario involving clocks at different floors of
    a high-rise building]

    1. In the gravitational scenario, if you have good enough
    measurement accuracy to distinguish the elapsed proper times
    of the clocks, then you cannot apply the equivalence principle
    (EP), because the curvature of spacetime is not negligible.
    2. Because of #1, your two scenarios do not correspond as you
    claim -- they are NOT "equivalent" because the EP does not
    apply.
    3. GR does NOT say "each HF's clock suddenly starts ticking faster
    than the AO's clock", because clocks always tick at their usual
    (intrinsic) rate [#]. IOW: a clock's proper tick rate is
    independent of its instantaneously co-moving inertial frame. --
    this is a direct consequence of Einstein's first postulate
    of SR, as it applies in GR.
    4. But you are not actually comparing clock tick rates, you are
    comparing their elapsed proper times. In GR a clock's elapsed
    proper time is computed by integrating the metric over its path
    through spacetime. The equation you use is the difference between
    two such integrals, applied to your specific physical situation.
    That difference is not due to different clock tick rates, but
    rather is due to the difference in the metric at their locations
    -- examine the derivation and you'll see it assumes equal proper
    (intrinsic) tick rates but different values of the metric.

    [#] But signals from a distant clock can tick at a
    different rate from that of a local, identical clock.
    This is due to the way such signals are measured, which
    is the basis of all types of redshift measurements.

    Bottom line: as before in your earlier scenarios, you have misunderstood
    basic relativity, and have misapplied the equivalence principle.

    Tom Roberts

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Tom Roberts on Sun Apr 17 08:03:00 2022
    On 4/16/22 12:57 AM, Tom Roberts wrote:

    Bottom line: the POE applies ONLY in regions of spacetime that are small enough that any curvature is negligible (compared to measurement
    accuracies). For the case you have in mind, with helper friends
    ("people") near a distant friend while the accelerated observer ("AO")
    roams the universe, those people span an enormous spatial region, over a
    very long time.



    The theory of special relativity places no limits AT ALL on the extent
    of spacetime. THAT is the domain of my scenario with acceleration.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Tom Roberts@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Mon Apr 18 15:46:23 2022
    On 4/17/22 3:03 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 4/16/22 12:57 AM, Tom Roberts wrote:
    Bottom line: the POE applies ONLY in regions of spacetime that are
    small enough that any curvature is negligible (compared to
    measurement accuracies). For the case you have in mind, with
    helper friends ("people") near a distant friend while the
    accelerated observer ("AO") roams the universe, those people span
    an enormous spatial region, over a very long time.

    The theory of special relativity places no limits AT ALL on the
    extent of spacetime. THAT is the domain of my scenario with
    acceleration.

    Sure. But you attempt to argue by "equivalence" to a situation in which
    a uniform gravitational field is present -- that is NOT Special
    Relativity, and that "equivalence" is NOT valid, as I explained earlier.

    Specifically: in flat spacetime for helper friends with equal proper accelerations, you claim that the pairwise distances [#] between helper
    friends are constant, because they are constant in the uniform-gravity spacetime you think is "equivalent". Your argument is invalid because
    the physical situations aren't actually equivalent -- the region
    involved is too large for the Principle of Equivalence to apply; for
    your case in flat spacetime those pairwise distances [#] are not
    constant, as one can explicitly calculate.

    [#] Pairwise distances are measured in the instantaneously
    co-moving inertial frame of the accelerating observer (AO).

    [This is getting tedious and overly repetitive. Unless you come up with something new, I won't continue.]

    Tom Roberts

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Tom Roberts on Mon Apr 18 14:17:57 2022
    On 4/18/22 9:46 AM, Tom Roberts wrote:
    Your argument is invalid because
    the physical situations aren't actually equivalent -- the region
    involved is too large for the Principle of Equivalence to apply

    The equivalence principle has no restrictions on the size of the region
    in which it is valid.

    [[Mod. note -- The EP applies if and only if we neglect tidal effects,
    i.e., if tidal effects are "small". But the size of tidal effects grows
    with the distance, so saying that tidal effects should be "small" (so
    that we can apply the EP) is essentially saying that the size of our
    region should be "small". So, effectively, the EP only applies in "small" regions, where the precise definition of "small" depends on the curvature
    of spacetime and your accuracy threshold for how small tidal effects need
    to be before it's ok to neglect them.

    For example, suppose we're considering some experiment near the Earth's surface, where we're measuring accelerations on the order of 1g. We might reasonably say that for this experiment, we're willing to apply the EP
    (i.e., neglect tidal effects) if the tidal accelerations are below 1e-6 g
    in magnitude, i.e., if the tidal accelerations are < 1 part-per-million
    of the Earth's Newtonian "little g". To satisfy that condition requires
    that our experimental region be (roughly) < 3 meters in diameter. That
    is, the tidal change in the Earth's Newtonian "little g" over a vertical distance of 3 meters is about 1 part-per-million. (In the horizontal
    direction the change is probably a bit smaller.) If our experimental
    region is larger than 3 meters in diameter, the tidal change in "little g"
    from one part of our apparatus to another part may be > 1 part-per-million,
    so we can't safely apply the EP across at our 1 part-per-million accuracy threshold.
    -- jt]]

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Tue Apr 19 07:19:49 2022
    On 4/18/22 9:46 AM, Tom Roberts wrote:
    Your argument is invalid because
    the physical situations aren't actually equivalent -- the region
    involved is too large for the Principle of Equivalence to apply


    Mike Fontenot replied (on 4/18/22 3:17 PM):

    The equivalence principle has no restrictions on the size of the region
    in which it is valid.


    [[Mod. note -- The EP applies if and only if we neglect tidal effects,
    i.e., if tidal effects are "small". But the size of tidal effects grows
    with the distance, so saying that tidal effects should be "small" (so
    that we can apply the EP) is essentially saying that the size of our
    region should be "small". So, effectively, the EP only applies in "small" regions, where the precise definition of "small" depends on the curvature
    of spacetime and your accuracy threshold for how small tidal effects need
    to be before it's ok to neglect them.

    There are NO "tidal effects" in my gravitational scenario (nor in my
    equivalent special relativity scenario, of course).

    Tidal effects arise when the gravitational field lines are NOT parallel,
    which occurs when the source of the gravitational field is a spherical distribution of mass, which acts as if all of the mass is concentrated
    at a point at the center of the sphere, giving an inverse-square
    variation of "g" with height).

    In my gravitational scenario, the gravitational lines are all EXACTLY
    PARALLEL, and perpendicular to the FLAT surface (of infinite extent) of
    the mass that the high-rise building is sitting on. That's why the
    field strength "g" in my scenario is (by design) independent of height
    ... it does NOT vary as the inverse-square of height.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Tom Roberts@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Wed Apr 20 10:57:24 2022
    On 4/19/22 2:19 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    The equivalence principle has no restrictions on the size of the
    region in which it is valid.

    Yes, it does, as has been explained several times in this thread.

    There are NO "tidal effects" in my gravitational scenario (nor in my equivalent special relativity scenario, of course).

    But a calculation shows that in SR, helper friends (HFs) with proper accelerations equal to that of the accelerated observer (AO), do NOT
    remain at constant proper distance from the AO, contrary to your claim.
    Look up Bell's spaceship paradox for an example calculation:
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bell%27s_spaceship_paradox

    Such constant proper distances requires the HFs and AO all execute Born
    rigid motion [#]. As is well known, that requires that "lower" HFs have
    larger proper accelerations, and "higher" HFs have smaller proper
    accelerations than the AO.

    [#] Born rigid motion is defined as all parts of the object
    having pairwise constant proper distances. Here the "object"
    is the collection of all HFs and the AO.

    Bottom line: in the not-really-equivalent scenario you gave, with a
    constant and uniform gravitational field, the HFs and AO all have equal
    proper accelerations, and their pairwise proper distances do remain
    constant. The Principle of Equivalence does NOT relate your two
    scenarios, and your argument is invalid.

    Tom Roberts

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Tom Roberts on Wed Apr 20 23:21:50 2022
    On 4/20/22 11:57 AM, Tom Roberts wrote:

    But a calculation shows that in SR, helper friends (HFs) with proper accelerations equal to that of the accelerated observer (AO), do NOT
    remain at constant proper distance from the AO, contrary to your claim.
    Look up Bell's spaceship paradox for an example calculation:
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bell%27s_spaceship_paradox


    I looked at that wiki page, and here's what they say:

    "A delicate thread hangs between two spaceships. They start accelerating simultaneously and equally as measured in the inertial frame S, thus
    having the same velocity at all times as viewed from S."

    So in the above scenario, according to the inertial frame "S", the two spaceships accelerate equally (and thus remain separated by a fixed
    distance). But in that scenario, the people in the spaceships would NOT
    agree that they were accelerating at the same rate, and they would NOT
    agree that their separation was constant. So that is a DIFFERENT
    scenario than the one I have described.

    In my scenario, the people who are accelerating conclude that their accelerations are exactly equal, and that their separations are exactly
    equal. The inertial observers there disagree.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Tom Roberts@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Fri Apr 22 21:45:25 2022
    On 4/21/22 1:21 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 4/20/22 11:57 AM, Tom Roberts wrote:
    But a calculation shows that in SR, helper friends (HFs) with
    proper accelerations equal to that of the accelerated observer
    (AO), do NOT remain at constant proper distance from the AO,
    contrary to your claim. Look up Bell's spaceship paradox for an
    example calculation:
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bell%27s_spaceship_paradox

    I looked at that wiki page, [...] So that is a DIFFERENT scenario
    than the one I have described.

    Yes it is, but it is an example of how to perform the calculation. You
    MUST perform the calculation, as you keep making incorrect claims.

    In my scenario, the people who are accelerating conclude that their accelerations are exactly equal, and that their separations are
    exactly equal.

    [You said earlier that their proper accelerations
    are exactly equal, and instead of "separations"
    you said "proper distances". Wishy-washy words
    like you use here are insufficient -- precision
    in thought and word is essential.]

    Your claim here is wrong. With equal proper accelerations, this
    collection of people is not executing Born rigid motion, and their
    (pairwise) proper distances change over time. Or the other way: with
    constant (pairwise) proper distances they do execute Born rigid motion,
    so their proper accelerations cannot be equal.

    You clearly have an incorrect mental image of this, which you doggedly
    cling to. The only way to disabuse yourself of that error is to actually perform the calculation. Simplify it: consider just the AO accelerating
    in the +x direction, and a single HF at a large negative value of x with
    the same proper acceleration; keep their proper accelerations constant
    and compute the proper distance between them (i.e. their distance apart measured in successive ICIFs of the AO). Be sure to use proper
    accelerations, and not accelerations relative to some inertial frame.

    [Alternative: look up "Born rigid motion" and understand it
    -- see what it is and how it differs from your scenario.]

    Tom Roberts

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Mon Apr 25 00:41:35 2022
    On 4/21/22 12:21 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 4/20/22 11:57 AM, Tom Roberts wrote:

    But a calculation shows that in SR, helper friends (HFs) with proper
    accelerations equal to that of the accelerated observer (AO), do NOT
    remain at constant proper distance from the AO, contrary to your claim.
    Look up Bell's spaceship paradox for an example calculation:
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bell%27s_spaceship_paradox

    I, Mike Fontenot wrote:

    I looked at that wiki page, and here's what they say:

    "A delicate thread hangs between two spaceships. They start accelerating simultaneously and equally as measured in the inertial frame S, thus
    having the same velocity at all times as viewed from S."

    So in the above scenario, according to the inertial frame "S", the two spaceships accelerate equally (and thus remain separated by a fixed distance). But in that scenario, the people in the spaceships would NOT agree that they were accelerating at the same rate, and they would NOT
    agree that their separation was constant. So that is a DIFFERENT
    scenario than the one I have described.

    In my scenario, the people who are accelerating conclude that their accelerations are exactly equal, and that their separations are exactly equal. The inertial observers there disagree.

    In the above paragraph, instead of saying

    "and that their separations are exactly equal",

    I SHOULD have said

    "and that their separations are constant."

    In Tom Roberts' scenario (which is the "Bell Paradox" scenario), the perpetually-inertial observers correctly conclude that, according to
    their inertial frame, the accelerating people are all accelerating at
    the same constant rate (and therefore that their separations are all
    equal and constant). The accelerating people do NOT agree with them.

    The perpetually-inertial observers are certainly entitled to set up that scenario, but that is a scenario that I have NO interest in at all.

    The scenario that I am interested in, is the scenario where it is the accelerated people who correctly conclude that their accelerations are
    all equal, and that their separations are all constant. In that
    scenario, perpetually-inertial observers do NOT agree with them.

    The REASON that I am solely interested in the immediately above scenario
    is because what I want to know IS the conclusion of the accelerating
    people, about how their ageing rates compare. THAT is what allows me to
    define a meaningful "NOW" instant for one of them. And that is what
    allows me to show that the CMIF simultaneity method is the ONLY correct simultaneity method for an accelerating observer.

    And once I know the relative ageing rates of the accelerating people in
    the above acceleration scenario, the equivalence principle immediately
    tells me the ageing rates of the stationary people in the equivalent gravitational scenario. Everything remains the same, except that the
    equal and constant accelerations of the people (directed along the
    straight line connecting them) are replaced by an equal and constant gravitational field acting on the stationary people (where the
    gravitational field is directed along the straight line connecting the
    people).

    Michael Leon Fontenot

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Tom Roberts@21:1/5 to Mike Fontenot on Mon May 2 09:36:20 2022
    On 4/25/22 2:41 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 4/21/22 12:21 AM, Mike Fontenot wrote:
    On 4/20/22 11:57 AM, Tom Roberts wrote:
    But a calculation shows that in SR, helper friends (HFs) with
    proper accelerations equal to that of the accelerated observer
    (AO), do NOT remain at constant proper distance from the AO,
    contrary to your claim.

    In Tom Roberts' scenario (which is the "Bell Paradox" scenario), the perpetually-inertial observers correctly conclude that, according to
    their inertial frame, the accelerating people are all accelerating at
    the same constant rate (and therefore that their separations are all
    equal and constant).

    You need to read more carefully. In the paragraph you quoted above, I specifically said "proper distance" -- and earlier in that post I
    clarified that this means the distance measured in the AO's
    instantaneously co-moving inertial frame (ICIF). That is NOT "according
    to their inertial frame", it is according to the AO's ICIF (which
    obviously changes over time as the AO is accelerating).

    The accelerating people do NOT agree with them.

    You claim the accelerating people measure proper distance, so they MUST
    agree with ANYBODY who also measures (or calculates) proper distance.
    After all, the (pairwise) proper distances are each unique and invariant
    (at any given point along the AO's worldline).

    The perpetually-inertial observers are certainly entitled to set up
    that scenario, but that is a scenario that I have NO interest in at
    all.

    And it is NOT what I was discussing. You misread what I wrote.

    The scenario that I am interested in, is the scenario where it is
    the accelerated people who correctly conclude that their
    accelerations are all equal, and that their separations are all
    constant.

    You may be "interested" in such a scenario, but it is inconsistent with relativity -- equal (proper) accelerations do NOT yield Born rigid
    motion (in which all pairwise proper distances remain constant).

    There are two choices:
    A) all have equal proper accelerations, in which case their
    pairwise proper distances are changing.
    or:
    B) All pairwise proper distances are constant, in which case
    "lower" people have larger proper accelerations than
    "higher" people (here "lower" people are behind "higher"
    people along the direction of acceleration).

    This is directly related to the Bell spaceship paradox. The fact that
    you don't realize that is a major part of your misunderstanding.

    In that scenario, perpetually-inertial observers do NOT agree with
    them.

    When the perpetually-inertial people make measurements and compute the
    proper distances, they MUST agree with the accelerated people (who do
    the same). Because such (pairwise) proper distances are each unique and invariant (at any given point along the AO's worldline).

    [... further discussion based on the above error]

    I give up. You keep repeating the same errors without reading what I
    write, so there's no point in continuing. Goodbye. (I'm surprised the moderators have let it go this long.)

    Tom Roberts

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to Tom Roberts on Wed May 4 12:11:51 2022
    On 5/2/22 2:36 AM, Tom Roberts wrote:

    [...]

    In a SINGLE SCENARIO:

    (1): YOU contend that the accelerating person (the AO) concludes that
    the separation between himself and his helper friend ("HF") is CONSTANT.

    (2): YOU contend that the perpetually-inertial observer ALSO concludes
    that the separation between the AO and the HF is CONSTANT.

    The special theory of relativity does NOT allow item (1) and item (2) to
    BOTH be true, in a SINGLE SCENARIO. In special relativity, a perpetually-inertial observer can NEVER agree with an accelerating
    observer for longer than a single instant.

    Michael Leon Fontenot

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Sun May 8 07:41:36 2022
    On 5/4/22 5:11 AM, I (Mike Fontenot) wrote:


    In a SINGLE SCENARIO:

    (1): YOU (Tom Roberts) contend that the accelerating person (the AO) concludes that
    the separation between himself and his helper friend ("HF") is CONSTANT.

    (2): YOU (Tom Roberts) contend that the perpetually-inertial observer ALSO concludes
    that the separation between the AO and the HF is CONSTANT.

    The special theory of relativity does NOT allow item (1) and item (2) to
    BOTH be true, in a SINGLE SCENARIO. In special relativity, a perpetually-inertial observer can NEVER agree with an accelerating
    observer for longer than a single instant.

    Michael Leon Fontenot


    The simplest way, to see that my statements above are true, is to use
    the well-known (and sacrosanct) length-contraction equation (LCE) of
    special relativity:

    According to a perpetually-inertial observer (PIO), a meter-stick
    stationary in any other frame that is moving wrt the PIO will be
    SHORTENED by the FACTOR

    gamma = sqrt( 1 / [ 1 - v * v ],

    where "v" is the current velocity of the other frame wrt the PIO's
    frame, and the asterisk denotes multiplication.

    At any instant in his life, the accelerating observer (AO) says that his yardstick is three feet long. But the PIO says the yardstick's length
    is 3 feet DIVIDED by gamma. Since gamma is greater than 1.0 when v is nonzero, the PIO says that the moving yardstick is shorter than three
    feet long.


    Michael Leon Fontenot

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Fontenot@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jul 11 19:40:42 2022
    I need to correct an error I made in an earlier post on this thread. I
    made the same error in my viXra paper, titled "A New Gravitational Time Dilation Equation", https://vixra.org/abs/2201.0015. Near the end of
    Section 1 of that paper, I wrote

    "Although the AO and the HF have different ages as the acceleration
    progresses, they each know, and agree about, what the relationship is
    between their respective ages. That establishes a "NOW" instant for
    them, that they both agree about."

    That statement is incorrect. The AO and the HF DON'T agree about the relationship between their ages.

    In Section 3, I gave the Rate Ratio equation:

    R(A, t) = [ 1 + L * A * sech^2 (A * t) ],

    which gives, according to the AO, the ratio of the HF's rate of ageing
    to the AO's rate of ageing. The acceleration "A" was taken to be
    positive, and thus R is greater than 1.0 when the AO is trailing, and
    the HF is leading. So the HF will be older than the AO, according to the AO.

    But if we make "A" negative, that makes the second term in the R
    equation negative, and R will then be less than 1.0.

    So for negative "A", the AO says that the HF is the younger one, not the
    older one. And the AO is no longer the trailing observer, he is now the
    leading observer.

    So by making "A" negative, we have effectively switched the roles of the
    AO and the HF. We can then say that, according to the HF, the AO is
    ageing less fast than the HF, by the ratio

    R2(A, t) = [ 1 - L * |A| * sech^2 (A * t) ].

    But the quantities R and R2 are NOT reciprocals (because their product
    is not equal to 1.0), and therefore the AO and the HF do NOT agree about
    the correspondence of their ages.

    That disagreement is of no importance to us though, because it is
    strictly the AO's view of the "NOW" moment that we want.

    The R2 equation IS of some use to us, though, because it also gives the viewpoint of the AO when he is accelerating AWAY FROM the home twin,
    rather than toward her.

    I have put this correction on the viXra repository (along with some
    other results), titled "Is the Equivalence Principle Schizophrenic? ...
    And a Summary, and a Correction",
    https://vixra.org/abs/2206.0133

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)